According to the Encyclopaedia
Britannica, John Locke defined consciousness as “the perception of what
passes in a man’s own mind.” I suppose that it is true that Locke said so,
although I cannot check it, for there is no reference added to the quotation,
which actually is to be expected in a work of that standing. Anyway, the
passage is not from the famous chapter XXVII “Of Identity and Diversity” in
Locke’s An Essay concerning Human
Understanding (first published in 1689, but this chapter was added in 1694).
Here Locke develops the idea of personal identity and links it to the idea of
consciousness. For instance, in §19 Locke says that “personal Identity
consists, not in the Identity of Substance, but ... in the Identity of consciousness
...” The idea of consciousness was not an invention of Locke. Already Plato and
Aristotle formulated theories on consciousness and the English word
“consciousness” existed already more than a century before Locke wrote his Essay. However, just as we can call
Descartes the father of epistemology because he first systematized scientific
methodology (see my blog last week), we can call Locke the father of consciousness
theories because he first gave the concept a full place in philosophy and
science.
As my quotation from the chapter on identity and
diversity in the Essay illustrates,
for Locke consciousness and substance – so mind and body, as we would say now –
were two different things. In this respect Locke’s approach of consciousness
was Cartesian. So for Locke it was basically possible that “the soul of a
prince, carrying with it the consciousness of the prince’s past life, enter and
inform the body of a cobbler” (§15 in chapter XXVII of the Essay), for the bodily characteristics of the prince were not part
of his personality. We still find this separation between mind (or
consciousness) and body in the modern discussion on personal identity, from
Bernard Williams in “The self and the future” (Philosophical Review 79/2: 161-180) till Derek Parsons in Reasons and Persons (1984) and
thereafter, and the so-called psychological-continuity theories of personal
identity still form the mainstream view on personal identity, despite alternative
views of, for instance, John Olson (The
human animal (1997)) and myself (see http://www.bijdeweg.nl/PersonalIdentity.htm).
Only now it becomes more and more accepted that substance and consciousness in
man, so mind and body, are fully integrated. For some this means that man is
nothing but a body or that man is a kind of biological machine, or how they see
it; anyway that man is a completely material being and that the mind is a kind
of epiphenomenal effect emerging from the human matter. Others, like me, prefer
a dual aspect view on man, which says that man can be considered in different
ways: as a biological body or as a conscious and thinking mind, although in the
end man is both together. I think that this view makes it also easier to
understand how in a certain sense man can survive his or her material dead.
With this remark I do not mean that man can survive in any religious sense, for
example as a soul, but the idea that mind as one of the two aspects of man
makes it possible to understand how culture can survive the bearers of a
certain culture; how ideas can remain to exist and have influence long after
the thinker of these same ideas who has written them down in books or on the
Internet has passed away. But maybe this is not as anti-Lockean as it seems on
the face of it, for didn’t Locke say in the §15 just quoted that “The body, as
well as the soul, goes to the making of a man” and that the cobbler who would
receive the soul of a prince still “would be the same cobbler to every one
besides himself”?
Monday, June 29, 2015
Monday, June 22, 2015
Descartes' tremendous idea
Science is a modern idea. In my last blog I wrote that
Montaigne was an essayist and a writer. He was also a keen observer. By writing
down his observations, Montaigne broadened our view on ourselves and
environment and our self-insight. But Montaigne was not a scientist; he was not
an investigator. In his time the idea of science was yet developing and by his
view that everything can be doubted Montaigne contributed to its development.
His adage was “What do I know?”, which would later find expression in the doubt
that Descartes used for laying the foundations of the ideas of knowledge and
consciousness with his famous words “I think so I am”. The idea of
consciousness was fully developed by John Locke, but we can see René Descartes
as the father of epistemology.
Descartes blamed many researchers of his time for not
working systematically. He reproached them that there was no line in the way
they worked. But then, so Descartes, it is impossible to get at the truth. What
we need is a method: certain and easy rules that lead us to true knowledge.
Moreover, Descartes was not satisfied with the old syllogistic logic of
Aristotle and the medieval scholastic logic. It’s so that they help systemize
existing knowledge and that they are useful in helping explain arguments to
other people, but they are not useful in getting new knowledge. For getting new
knowledge we need something else: A research methodology. Therefore Descartes
wrote his Rules for the Direction of the
Mind. However, this work, written in 1628 or just thereafter, was not
published before 1684, so after his death. And the first publication was not in
the original Latin but it was a Dutch translation. The first Latin edition came
out in 1701. This work and other ideas on methodology made Descartes the founder
of epistemology.
These Rules
and generally Descartes’ approach of science gave us not only a new way of
investigating nature, including man, but it gave us also a new view on
knowledge. Or rather, it lead not only to a new view on knowledge but it changed the whole idea of knowledge, because we got a new way to experience what is
around us. Before Descartes, from Aristotle till the Middle Ages, those
experiences were considered knowledge that could be fit in a coherent way in
what we already knew. New experiences had to be fitted in frames accepted by
tradition. But from Descartes on only those experiences were considered
knowledge that could be justified by the right method. Knowledge became what
stands the tests of science. Four centuries later Karl R. Popper would sharpen
the question what knowledge is: what we think to know has always to be
formulated that way that we can test it. Montaigne and Descartes introduced the
relation between doubt and knowledge. Popper made doubt a part of knowledge.
Descartes did not go that far. He believed yet that
absolute certain knowledge is possible. It was only a matter of time to get it.
But what he did do was founding knowledge no longer on experiences, so on what
we think to see and hear as such, but on method, so on the way we see and
think. Already this was a tremendous idea. It was a new idea, an idea that
would lead to a new world: the world we live in today.
Monday, June 15, 2015
What everybody knows
In his essay “Of virtue” (Essays II-29) Montaigne writes about the case of a Turkish lord who
in vain tried to shoot a hare. Also his dogs didn’t succeed to catch the animal.
Therefore the lord concluded that the hare had been protected by his fate. This
made Montaigne remark: “This story may serve ... to let us see how flexible our
reason is to all sorts of images.”
A few years ago I wrote a blog about Festinger’s
theory of cognitive dissonance, which says that when there is a gap between
what we believe and what actually is the case we try to adapt the facts to our
believes (see my blog dated Dec. 31, 2012). In Montaigne’s example the Turkish
lord was so convinced of his own qualities and the qualities of his dogs that
he couldn’t imagine that he failed. Something different must have been the case
so that he could maintain his belief in himself and his dogs: There was a
higher power that protected the hare. The much simpler explanation that he wasn’t
a good hunter couldn’t be true in his eyes. It’s a clear instance of the
reduction of cognitive dissonance in the sense of the theory of Festinger.
So far, so good. However, I wrote – which is generally
accepted – that it was Festinger with his team who first formulated the theory
of cognitive dissonance, but now we see that four centuries before Montaigne
expressed already the same idea. Must we say now that Festinger and his
co-workers didn’t invent this theory but that it was Montaigne who did, even
though he didn’t call it that way? I think that there are arguments to say so,
but that we can better stick to the opinion that Festinger & Co. are the
inventors.
When I studied sociology long ago, many people said to
me: A sociologist investigates what everybody already knows. It is a common
opinion but it is easy to show that it’s nonsense. Nonetheless, there is some
truth in it. Often, sociologists do investigate what “everybody” already knows,
but it is not so that everybody knows that “everybody” knows (see note). Or
some facts are only known to certain groups but the policy makers don’t know it
or, if they do, they don’t believe them. Then it’s useful that social
scientists investigate the matter. Do teachers really make such long hours as
they say? Well, let’s investigate it and compare it with the work load of other
of other employees. Or, what is often heard: “All foreigners are criminals –
with the exception of my neighbour” (forgetting that once you have passed the
border of your country you yourself are also a foreigner). So let’s investigate
it and show that this prejudice simply isn’t true. By the way, it can happen
that prejudices are true, for – as
Hans-Georg Gadamer explained – a prejudice
actually is nothing but an opinion that is not well established by the facts;
but it can exist because we don’t know the facts or don’t have them at hand.
It’s true, in practice prejudices are often unreasonable, biased opinions,
dislikes and so on, but then it’s just the challenge for investigators to demonstrate
that – or to topple their own prejudices.
Be it is it may, Montaigne was not a systematic
investigator. Even more, in his days systematic research in the modern sense
did not yet insist but the idea was yet under construction so to speak, to
which he in fact also contributed, for example by his view on “doubt”.
Montaigne was an essayist and writer. He was a keen observer who wrote down
what he saw and thought. Investigating opinions, views, ideas etc, – called
“hypotheses” in the scientific jargon – in a systematic and methodological way
and testing the truth of them is what investigators do and what Montaigne did
not do in his Essays. Therefore maybe
we can say that Montaigne was the inventor of the idea of cognitive dissonance – if he was – but not the inventor of
the theory. It was Festinger with his
team who was the latter. Generally it is so that there are many good and useful
ideas in society but often it’s uncertain what the truth in them is, even if
they appear to be useful. That’s what we science need for. But perhaps the present
blog is only a case of cognitive dissonance reduction that I wrote for
confirming my own prejudice.
Monday, June 08, 2015
Art as a daily practice
In his “Afterword” to Michel de Certeau’s Culture in the Plural, Tom Conley writes:
“[For de Certeau] ‘culture’ needs to be understood not as a monument
celebrating human mastery of nature but, to the contrary, and more modestly, as
collective ways or manners of
thinking and doing. ... [Culture] is marked by heterogeneity of practices,
styles, modes or fashions of selectively and affectively producing (but not
arrogating) habitable space.” (Conley, p. 151). In other words, according to de
Certeau culture is not something highbrow, as it is often seen, but it is the
way we do what we do, and it can even refer to the most banal actions and kinds
of behaviour. In this view, culture consists of modes of doings characteristic
for certain groups or even societies.
When I read de Certeau’s Culture in the Plural (and other books by him) and Conley’s
“Afterword” for the first time several years ago, this view was not new to me.
I subscribed to it already long before I had ever heard of Michel de Certeau,
let alone that I had read his articles and books. I had borrowed the idea from
authors in the field of cultural anthropology. But are both views – the
“highbrow view” and the view of culture as the mode of daily practice – really
so different today? Take the picture at the top of this blog. I have taken it
on the yearly art market in my town, one week ago. What you see there is my
stall with some of my photos and books and on the background a super market.
Before or after having done their shopping, many people made a walk along the
stalls of the art market. Some bought a piece of art; most didn’t. Is there a better
example of the growing contemporary integration of culture as the mode of daily
practice and highbrow culture, which is often supposed to be at a distance from
the hectic of daily routine? Art is no longer something we need to watch in the
serene atmosphere of a separate temple-like building, be it a theatre or a
museum, and that we take in full of awe. Art is no longer something performed
by demigods and explained by expert interpreters. No, art has become for
everybody and by everybody. You can enjoy it everywhere and do it everywhere,
as a part of your normal activities; also when you are in a supermarket or before
and after shopping. It has become a part of the daily practice and it is
consumed as easy as a cup of tea or a bag of chips. Isn’t it what we have aimed
for, when we talked about the democratization of culture? Oh, and don’t forget
the milk or the mayonnaise.
Source: Michel de Certeau’s, Culture in the Plural. Minneapolis/London:
University of Minnesota Press, 1997. Tom Conley, “Afterword: A Creative Swarm”,
in id., pp. 149-175.
Monday, June 01, 2015
A bird in a cage
Last week, I stated that man is a prisoner of his or
her own habits and routine. Even if the door of the prison is open, s/he
doesn’t use the opportunity to escape, as any animal would do. Is it true? Maybe
man is more rational than animals. Why should s/he escape when the door is
open? Once you are free, you have to decide for yourself; not only now and then
but always. You can do anything you like, indeed. However, if everything is
possible in the end nothing is possible. For how to choose? Moreover, once you
take a step, it limits the number of the next steps you can take. When, for
instance, on your own walk through life you reach the bank of a river, your
choice where to go seems almost without limit, but once you choose to spring in
the river, your number of choices will be reduced to four: Going back, swimming
to the other bank, giving in by following the stream, or becoming recalcitrant by
going against the current. And do you know where it will bring you, whichever
decision you take? Most men are not adventurous and don’t have enough insight
in order to be able the take the right choices in all unexpected circumstances
– or at least in most – so that it is wiser to stay where you are: In your
cage. And because you know that the door is open, you keep the freedom to leave
when you get an idea what to do outside, with the possibility to go back when
you like. Seen that way it is not unreasonable to stay where you are and limit
your space of freedom in practice to your cage.
Or is this freedom an illusion? For whether the door
of the prison is open or closed makes for most people no difference at all!
Even if it is open, they don’t see that it is open. They see no cage. They
simply think that they are free and can go where they like. Why this is so has
been made clear by the feminist philosopher Marilyn Frye. Although her metaphor
has been developed for explaining the idea of oppression, I think it can also
be used for making clear why many people have the illusion that they are free.
Let me first give a long quote from Frye’s article “Oppression”, where she puts
forward her picture of the bird cage:
“Consider a
birdcage. If you look very closely at just one wire in the cage, you cannot see
the other wires. If your conception of what is before you is determined by this
myopic focus, you could look at that one wire, up and down the length of it,
and be unable to see why a bird would not just fly around the wire any time it
wanted to go somewhere. Furthermore, even if, one day at a time, you myopically
inspected each wire, you still could not see why a bird would gave trouble
going past the wires to get anywhere. There is no physical property of any one
wire, nothing that the closest
scrutiny could discover, that will reveal how a bird could be inhibited or
harmed by it except in the most accidental way. It is only when you step back,
stop looking at the wires one by one, microscopically, and take a macroscopic
view of the whole cage, that you can see why the bird does not go anywhere; and
then you will see it in a moment. It will require no great subtlety of mental
powers. It is perfectly obvious that the bird is surrounded by a network of
systematically related barriers, no one of which would be the least hindrance
to its flight, but which, by their relations to each other, are as confining as
the solid walls of a dungeon.”
This picture used by Frye for grasping why it is so
difficult to see why and when oppression exists can also be used for grasping
why many people think that they are free, even when they actually live in a
cage. For most people just stand too near to the wires and see only the wire
that is right in front of their eyes. This gives them the idea that they are
free: Isn’t it so that it is easy to go out by walking around the bar? However,
if they would do a few steps back they would see that they are caged in ... and
maybe they would see also that there is a door that is open.
Quotation from Marilyn Frye, “Oppression” on
http://people.terry.uga.edu/dawndba/4500Oppression.html
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)