Monday, October 31, 2016
Facing death
Thursday, October 13, 2016
Framing the mind
If framing is a way of organizing our experiences, as
Erving Goffman puts it, then misframing can be a source of a lot of trouble and
a source of manipulation as well. Moreover a situation we are confronted with
can be that way that we don’t have a scheme for it: We are puzzled about what
is going on.
In his book Frame
analysis Goffman devotes a big part to examining what can go wrong with
framing. Sometimes errors in framing or discord about what is going on is even a
matter of dead and life. Indeed, framing is not an “innocent” affair but it is
substantial for meaningful action, for in many respects framing and acting are
one. Didn’t the sociologist W.I. Thomas say some 25 years before Goffman
published his book that “if
men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences”? For
sustaining the same view, Goffman quotes another sociologist, namely Aron
Gurwitsch, who said that “to experience an object amounts to being confronted
with a certain order of existence” (see Frame
Analysis p. 308). Misframing, so Goffman, will involve the framer in “the
breeding of wrongly oriented behavior” (ibid.).
But, as he continues, “then the misperception of a fact can involve the
importation of a perspective that is itself radically inapplicable, which will
itself establish a set, a whole grammar of expectations, that will not work.
The actor will then find himself using not the wrong word but the wrong
language. And in fact, this metaphor is also an actual example. If, as
Wittgenstein suggested, ‘To understand a sentence means to understand a language’,
then it would seem that speaking a sentence presupposes a whole language and
tacitly seeks to import its use.” (id.
pp. 308-309) Everybody who knows more than one language knows how much it is
true that a langue gives you a framework of the world and how the same sound
spoken within one language frame can mean something very different within
another language frame, with all its consequences. When a Frisian – a speaker
of a minority language in the North of the Netherlands – says “it kin net”, he means the opposite of what a
Dutchman thinks he does if he wrongly interprets it as “’t kan net”, as often happens. For although the
Frisian says “it cannot”, this
Dutchman thinks that he means that “it just
can”, so that it’s just possible (with sometimes fatal consequences).
Goffman’s
remark on Wittgenstein brings me to philosophy. Also here we find the idea of
framing everywhere, but often in another wording. Thomas Kuhn analyzed how the
transition from one theoretical paradigm to another leads to a scientific
revolution. But what else is such a paradigm shift than looking at the world
through a new frame? And actually it is so that theories are frames of a lower
level that are continuously renovated, polished and painted until the wood has
become so rotten that the frame has to be replaced by a new structure.
When Gilbert Ryle
attacked Descartes’ idea that man is a kind of machine with a ghost in it that
steers the machine (the body), he introduced the idea of category mistake. Once
in a blog I explained this idea with the example of a river. A river consists
of a countless number of water molecules. Nevertheless it is a category mistake
to say that a single water molecule streams. It is not the water molecule that streams
but the river does. So if we want to
study fluvial processes like erosion or the velocity of the flow, we do not
study the movements of the water molecules but we study the river. Nevertheless
it is possible to study the river molecules as such, just as it is possible to
study the river and fluvial processes. And so it is also a category mistake, I
continued in the same blog, if we confuse brain and mind. It is true, as a
river cannot exist apart from the water molecules that produce it, so also the
mind cannot exist apart from the neurons and what else makes up the brain. In
this sense the mind is the brain. Nevertheless it is a category mistake to
reduce a typical phenomenon of the mind like thoughts to a phenomenon of the
brain and its neurons. It is not our brain that thinks but our mind does, i.e.
“we” do. But as we can study the river molecules and the fluvial processes, we
can study the brain and the mind. It’s simply a matter of perspective; it’s simply
a matter of aspect. Seen from the view that I have developed in my last blogs,
is it then too far-fetched to say that a category mistake is nothing else but
using the wrong frame? And that confusing brain and mind (and reducing the mind
to the brain) is also nothing else but applying the wrong frame? In many
respects, science is a matter of developing frames and then making the right
choice.
Monday, October 10, 2016
Frame analysis
Photographic frames are actually nothing but instantiations
of what are called “cognitive schemas” elsewhere in these blogs: schemas that
help organize what you see; that let out what is unimportant; and bring to the
foreground what is relevant for you. It’s a term that is especially used in
linguistics and psychology. The philosopher Antonio Damasio calls them “maps”,
while the term “frame” is common in sociology for the phenomenon (although the
word is also often used in psychology). The classic book on “frame analysis” in
sociology still is the one by Erving Goffman with the same title, published in 1974.
Maybe the subtitle of this book describes best what framing is about: The
organization of experience. The photo of the napalm girl discussed by me last
week shows well how this works.
Goffman’s Frame
Analysis is quite a thick book (nearly 600 ages) and in my blogs I can’t do
justice to it, but let me pick a few elements from it. As we just have seen,
for Goffman framing is a matter of organizing experience. More exactly, for him
framing is a method we use for defining a situation we are involved in; so it
is a way to give it an interpretation. He sees frames as “principles of
organization which govern events – at least social ones – and our subjective
involvement in them” (pp. 10-11). For instance, suddenly I hear a bang and I
see people running. I wonder what is happening and what I have to do. Is it an
explosion? Is it a terrorist attack? Does it come from the exhaust pipe of a
car? Depending on how I interpret the bang, so how I frame it, and the reason I
am there – am I a passer-by, a policeman or do I live there? – I decide what to
do: Nothing, or going to the site for getting more information, calling for
help, running away, etc. A frame is individual, as Goffman says a few pages
further, it is subjective and, as I want to add – but certainly Goffman says it
elsewhere in his book – it has consequences for our behaviour: from doing
nothing and accepting as it is till taking action.
Most framing doesn’t happen explicitly and
consciously. Goffman’s explanation is a bit complicated, so let me say it in my
own words: As soon as someone recognizes a situation, he or she automatically
applies a framework or schema of interpretation. Since everyone has gone
through a shorter or longer period of education and internalization, initially he
or she falls back on the concepts and standard interpretations typical for his
or her culture when interpreting an event or situation. Goffman talks here of
“primary frameworks”. So if we see someone taking a book from a shelf in a
certain type of building and giving a sheet of paper to another person, we
automatically apply the framework “buying a book” (p. 21; the example is mine).
Primary frameworks can be of two kinds, so Goffman:
natural and social. Again I want to use my own words. A framework is “natural”
– not to confuse it with the term “natural frame” as I used it in my blog last
week – if it is purely physical and if its meaning does not depend on the
willful agency and intentionality of other people. On the other hand it is
“social”, if it gets its meaning from the wills, aims and intentions of others.
So a certain object is for us just a round thin piece of copper if considered
in the natural way or a five-cent piece if interpreted within a social
framework. (cf. pp. 21-22) Dealing
with objects within a natural frame requires instrumental action, while within
a social frame it involves rule-guided action.
By applying frames we constitute what we see and
experience. Often frames are shared among individuals in the sense that they
apply more or less the same frames to the same situations or events. Then all
share an understanding of what it is that is going on and what everyone is
doing, and then the frame concerned is “effectively correct” (cf. p. 301). In this way shared frames
make that people stick together so to speak.
Framing the world
Photos give a representation of reality. At least many
people think so. But do they really do? Recently I had a photo exhibition in my
town in which I tried to make clear that they don’t. The photos showed
landscapes, city views and the like but all had, what I would call, “natural”
frames. Often photos on an exhibition are put in wooden, plastic or metal frames,
but I had taken the photos that way that the frame was in the photo itself, for example because I had taken a photo
through a window together with the window frame (see for example the photo
above). Of course, you cannot capture the whole world in one picture, so a
photo must have an edge, but what many people don’t realize is that just the
edge makes that the photo doesn’t give an objective view, but that it is
subjective because there is an edge.
The edge directs the contents of the photo and makes that it presents a
perspective on the world and that it is a subjective interpretation of the
world. In other words, the edge of a photo functions like a frame. In order to
stress this and to make the viewers of my photos aware of it, I had the photos on
my exhibition provided with natural frames.
In sociology, a
frame is a set of concepts and theoretical perspective on how we perceive
reality. Framing is the social and perspectival construction of a phenomenon. The
frame tells us what is valuable and it excludes what isn’t, because we don’t
find it interesting; because it distracts; because we want to ignore it; and so
on. Actually in psychology it is the same but the difference is that psychology
concentrates on other themes than sociology does – which just makes that the
sociological and psychological perspectives are also frames! – Prejudices and
testimonies are instances of such frames. Prejudices are ways to order the
world and to pigeon-hole persons and phenomena. And when an accident has
happened and a policeman asks the witnesses what they have seen, he will hear
different stories, for each person interprets what took place from a different point
of view.
Framing can have quite extreme and improbable effects.
Take this psychological experiment:
Imagine you are asked to watch a video in which six
people – three in white shirts and three in black shirts – pass basketballs
around. While you watch, you must keep a silent count of the number of passes
made by the people in white shirts. At some point, a gorilla – actually a man
in a gorilla suit – strolls into the middle of the action, faces the camera and
thumps its chest, and then leaves, spending nine seconds on screen. Would you
see the gorilla? I think you’ll say “yes” but actually half of the test persons
did not: Their frame of attention was counting the passes which made that much
what didn’t fit this frame was excluded from their attention, including the
gorilla facing the camera. (source: http://theinvisiblegorilla.com/gorilla_experiment.html)
To take yet a photographic example: Recently there was
much to do on Facebook about the famous photo of a little Vietnamese girl hurt
by napalm and fleeing from her village that had been bombed with napalm (https://geschotenindeoorlog.files.wordpress.com/2013/10/vietnam-napalm-girl1.jpg).
The photo is very dramatic. However in order to emphasize the drama – and with
right, I think – the photographer had cut off the right part of the photo,
which showed a relaxed soldier looking at the camera in his hands (https://pbs.twimg.com/media/Bj5h_YaCIAE2Jom.jpg:large).
If the photographer wouldn’t have cropped the picture, it would have been less
dramatic: A matter of framing.
Compared with the photo of the napalm girl, my photos
with natural frames are not dramatic. Their contents is innocent. However, they
show what you can do with a frame, and what we in fact all do every time when
we look at something: Frames stress what we want or expect to see, just as in
my photos the frames emphasize landscapes and their beauty, or the dullness of
a rainy day. But actually we don’t know what happens outside the frames and
where they have been taken.
My photos with natural frames can be viewed here:
https://www.flickr.com/photos/photographybytheway/albums/72157657516004509
Monday, September 26, 2016
When science fails
Progress in science is a matter of developing theories
that are better than the existing ones. A new theory is better if it explains
phenomena that the old theory fails to explain, although they are within its
range and should have been explained by it. Or the new theory gives a more
plausible and simpler explanation of the facts. Of course, with the help of
some additional suppositions it may be possible to give the old theory a new or
broader basis, but with each additional supposition the old theory becomes more
complicated and by that more unlikely. The rule of thumb in science is the
simpler the better and generally it works that way. So, many old theories have quitted
the scene in exchange for new ones that played their parts better. Now we know
that the sun doesn’t orbit around the sun but that the opposite is the case. We
know that there is no ether that fills empty spaces but that a vacuum is really
possible. And we know now that life cannot originate from dead matter. How
progress works in science has been summarized by Karl Popper in a well-known
scheme:
P1 > TT > EE
> P2
In words: If we have a problem that we can’t explain with
the old theory (P1), we revise it or develop a completely new theory (TT). Then
we perform experiments (EE) in order to test our new ideas, and if the new
ideas are confirmed, the old theory has been improved or replaced in favour of the
new one. However, usually we see then new problems (P2) and the cycle starts again.
Since here in my presentation we start with the idea of a theory that appears
to have mistakes, we might describe the process of theory evolution also this
way:
TT1 > P > TT2
(tentative) > EE > TT2
Since TT2 is better than TT1 Popper talked here of
error elimination. This implies that actually the old theory has failed,
because it contained mistakes. But this is how scientific progress works and
there is no other approach. And often it is so that the old theory has been
used for a longer or shorter time to everyone’s satisfaction, despite its
mistakes.
TT1 can also fail for another other reason: Not because
it has been replaced by a better theory but because it is bad science. That’s
what we have seen in my last blog. If we look at the first scheme, then the
trouble is not that P that can’t be explained by TT but we think that TT has
explained P but the explanation is false. It is because the tests that seem to
substantiate TT have not been well done. So there is a failure in the
performance of EE. This can happen by accidental occurrences, but usually it is
so that the methods of investigation have not been well applied by ignorance,
negligence, lack of money or something like that, or in order to please the one
who pays the investigation or even by fraud. In other words, the tests failed
because of bad science. If it happens now and then it’s a blot on science.
However, if it happens too often and on a large scale, sooner or later it will
lead to a crisis. Then the schemes are no longer as shown above but they have
become:
P1 > TT > EE
> P2
and
TT1 > P > TT2
(tentative) > EE > TT2.
When the failures come to light we have a crisis in
science and the schemes as just represented stand for regress in science. And
that’s what we see now in social psychology. From a methodological point of
view the rules are simple: Besides a strict and correct application of the
methodical prescriptions any investigation has to be replicated, if possible by
other investigators in another setting and with another set-up. But often there
are many reasons not to replicate an “old” experiment. Practical reasons,
financial reasons and human reasons, for little credit can be gained by affirming
what has already been said by others (and if the original investigation has
been well performed, this will be the result). But a crisis in social
psychology does not hurt only social psychology itself (or any other science
that is hit by such a crisis, as the case may be), but it has wider
consequences. Results are applied. Convinced that the psychological investigations
have been well done, therapists have put their outcomes into practice. In
philosophy they have affected the view on man. Etc.
The key question is how it could come that far. If
we don’t give it an answer it can happen again, in psychology and elsewhere. There
is a name for the present problem: Replication crisis. It’s a name that points
already to its solution. But who will be prepared to tackle the problem, as
usually it is so that it doesn’t bring much to you if you do old wine in new
bottles?
Monday, September 19, 2016
Keep smiling
Take the case of intentionally smiling which should make
you feel better. This so-called facial feedback hypothesis had been discovered
in 1988 by the German psychologist Fritz Strack and his team. The investigators
took 92 students who had to put a pencil either between their teeth (which made
them smile) or between their lips (which made them pout) and then judge funny
cartoons. In the former case they found the cartoons funnier than in the latter
case. How this
mechanism worked was not clear but it was applied by many behavioural therapists.
However, in order to ensure that research results are correct – for instance that
they are not caused by factors not studied in the investigation – any research should
have to be repeated. Therefore, recently, at the instigation of Strack,
seventeen laboratories in the USA, Canada and Europe performed replication
tests. Maybe that it wasn’t known how the facial feedback hypothesis worked
should have been a warning, for it came out that it had to be refuted. How
pity, for I used the effect sometimes when I felt tired at the end of a long bike ride with
still many kilometres to go: I simply straightened my back, lifted my head, looked
around and smiled. This gave me again the mood to go on with a decent speed. It
was not that I was less tired then, but it felt so.
The facial feedback hypothesis is not the only result
in social psychology that recently has been rejected after replication. To take
another case mentioned in my blogs: We tend to walk slower, when we see old people
passing by, or also when we have read a text about old people with words like
old, slow etc. Also this psychological classic appeared not to be true. Even
more, when investigators tried to replicate about hundred of such “facts”, two
third could not be validated. Combined with recent cases of research fraud we
can say that social psychology is in dire straits.
What does all this mean? The refuted investigations
helped build a certain philosophical image of man. Psychologically they painted
man as a kind of physical dope that is the outcome of hidden mechanisms that work
independent of the will: If we are funny, happy, helpful, sad, angry, nice etc.
we are often so despite ourselves. Now I don’t want to deny that man is the
result of hidden processes in some way. Too much points to the fact that most
of what we do is “decided” on an unconscious level, but apparently how this
takes place is not as simple as suggested by the now rejected psychological
studies. Apparently we are not the kind of automatically behaving persons we
had come to think we are on the basis of the rejected studies. Man appears to be
structured in a different way and – let me formulate it carefully – there might
be more elbow room for a free will than the studies suggested. This may
especially be so, if we accept that there need not be a contradiction between
the fact that what we do is prepared by unconscious processes within us and the
idea that we have a free will, as I have explained before.
Nevertheless, when I make a bike tour and I become
tired, I still can decide to make a smile, for whatever the investigators say,
to my feeling it works. Already simply the idea of smiling cheers me up. Maybe
it is a kind of placebo-effect and it works because I think that it works, and just that is what makes that I am going to
ride better. But my adagio is: If it works, it works. So, I keep smiling. Why
not you too?
Monday, September 12, 2016
Wittgenstein and the concept of rationality
Countertenor
Philippe Jaroussky and his ensemble Atarserse in the TivoliVredenburg concert
hall
In my last blog we have seen that we can act in a
rational way although what we do is not necessarily rational according to the
utility theory in economics. But what is rationality? On the Internet, you can find
many definitions, some better, some worse, but let me say it this way: Actions
are rational if they contribute to our present purposes. This is rather vague
and I could add yet a phrase like “in the best way”, but I think that the essence
of what I mean is clear. So, if I want to go from my house to the TivoliVredenburg
concert hall in Utrecht, I can take the train, my car or my bike. Each of these
means is rational in view of the purpose of going there. Moreover I can add
some criteria, like “in the cheapest way”, “as quick as possible”, “conveniently”
or what more, and then I can make my definite choice. So in order to make our
choices, we often have to add secondary purposes. Seen that way, it is not
obvious that our purposes are economic in the first place. It’s quite well
possible that our choices are not rational in an economic sense, although they
are rational of a kind. It’s a thing that economists – and politicians as well
– often forget and it’s why Daniel Kahneman, by showing this, received the
Nobel Prize. I can say it also in this manner: Rationality is not an intrinsic
property of our actions. It depends on the context.
Although Wittgenstein didn’t develop an explicit
theory of rationality, just that rationality is context-dependent, becomes
clear from his work, especially if we look at his idea of language game. In his
Philosophical Investigations (PI) he
writes: “Consider for
example the proceedings that we call ‘games’. I mean board-games, card-games,
ball-games, Olympic games, and so on. What is common to them all? ... [I]f you
look at them you will not see something that is common to all, but similarities, relationships, and a whole series of them at
that. ... Look for example at board-games, with their multifarious
relationships. Now pass to card-games; here you find many correspondences with
the first group, but many common I features drop out, and others appear. When
we pass next to ballgames, much that is common is retained, but much is
lost.—Are they all ‘amusing’? Compare chess with noughts and crosses. Or is
there always winning and losing, or competition between players? Think of
patience. In ball games there is winning and losing; but when a child throws
his ball at the wall and catches it again, this feature has disappeared. [Etc.]
[T]he result of this examination is: we see a complicated network of
similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes overall similarities,
sometimes similarities of detail.” (PI 66). In my words: A game is a certain game because of a set of rules
that apply only to this game. A specific rule is out of place if applied in
another game, unless it happens that it explicitly belongs to that other game as
well and fits in its set of rules. But usually this is mere chance. Usually a
rule is only valid in the context of other rules with which it constitutes a
certain game (like football, bridge, chess, bicycle race ...). Nonetheless we
bring all these different games together under one heading: “games”. It is
because we think that they have something in common and that they are similar
in relevant respects. Here Wittgenstein says: “I can think of no better
expression to characterize these similarities than ‘family resemblances’; for
the various resemblances between members of a family: build, features, colour
of eyes, gait, temperament, etc. etc. overlap and criss-cross in the same way.—
And I shall say: ‘games’ form a family.” (PI 67)
What has this all to do with rationality? We have
seen that we often talk of “game” but that we can fill in this concept in
different ways. It is the context constituted by the specific rules that make
up a specific game. It’s the same with “rationality”. Rationality is not a univocal
concept that can be filled in in only one way: by money values. There are also
other ways to express the idea: positive or negative feelings, for instance. Or
speed or convenience. Nevertheless all these interpretations have enough in
common to use one word for it: Rationality. But this doesn’t mean that what is
rational in one context need also be so in another one, just as we don’t say
that a cyclist has scored a goal when he finishes first.
Monday, September 05, 2016
The rationality of economic behaviour
... After two hours I saw a direction sign to a camping site. I took a hotel. Was it rational? ...
Let me repeat an example from my last blog: Someone
offers you a gamble on the toss of a coin. If the coin shows tails, you lose €
100,-, and if it shows heads you win € 150,-. Would you accept it? The expected
value of the gamble is positive, for you can gain more than you can lose.
Therefore the best you can do is accept the offer, or so the economic utility
theory says. Nevertheless, most of us don’t, although we would do if we could
win € 200,-, and probably we would also accept the gamble if we could repeat it
hundred times, which is just as the utility tell us to do since it is rational,
while refusing isn’t. Therefore we have a problem: Is it irrational to refuse
the gamble since the utility theory tells us that we have to accept it? This is
what I assumed in the last few blogs, but it is correct? I think that the
difference between what the utility theory tells us to do and what we actually
do says more about the limited view on rationality of the utility theory than about
the rationality of man’s behaviour.
Let me give another example. Recently I have travelled
round and camped in my tent in Austria. When I left the country on the last day
of my holiday, it was late and the homeward drive was too long to do it yet the
same day. Therefore I had to overnight in Germany. After two hours I saw a
direction sign to a camping site. I took a hotel. Was it rational?
Let’s see what the utility theory tells me. I have my
tent and everything I need for camping with me plus enough to eat for the
breakfast. A night on the camping site costs €25,-. The night in the hotel with
breakfast costs € 100,-. So, I save 75,- euros by camping. The expected value
of going to the camping site is positive, which makes it rational to camp.
However, I am tired after a long day, and to pitch my tent will take me an
hour. Then I have to go to the restaurant, which is next to the hotel. Sleeping
in the hotel will be more pleasant and I have a personal bathroom there. I
don’t need to break up my tent next morning. I just leave, and the only thing I
want to do is going home as soon as possible. Taking a hotel is simply more
comfortable. However, what is the expected value of comfort? Well, if you ask
me to give its money value, I must say that I cannot. For me it’s a value in
itself. And here we are at the heart of the problem. Comfort is a subjective
feeling and we cannot give at a money value, although I must admit that I wouldn’t
have taken a hotel for € 250,- a night (but then I would have felt myself a bit
unhappy at the camping site for this night; and even more tired). To keep it
short, economic reasoning based on the utility theory has a limited idea of
rationality. It can express rationality only in terms of figures, preferably in
money values. But often much what makes life valuable can’t be expressed in money
and much of what we do is not done by us because of a positive expected money
value (utility), but because we enjoy it, because we like the style of a
certain action, because, it pleases our wife or husband, or someone else; and
so on. But if a theory can explain our actions only if and insofar as we can ascribe
money values to them, it must fail, sometimes or in most cases. Generally,
economic theories can explain what we do only if they can compute what we do in
terms of money. However, that they can’t compute money values for many human
actions, doesn’t mean these actions are not rational. It means only that they
apply an idea of rationality that is too limited for most what man does. Man’s
behaviour is not irrational if it doesn’t fit the utility theory but often it’s
simply rational in another way.
And how about the first example of this blog? Why don’t
most of us accept the gamble? The surest thing you can do is to refuse. Most
people prefer certainty and why should you take a risk to lose money if the
possible benefit is minimal? In most situations playing safe is the best
choice, and it will spare you a big fuss. Certainty is what many people prefer,
and tell me, why wouldn’t it be rational?
Monday, August 29, 2016
Being rational (2)
Since the Swiss mathematician Daniel Bernoulli developed
in 1738 what is now called the utility theory, it has been the mainstream approach
in economics for explaining how people make their choices. It supposes that the
relationship between the psychological value or desirability of money (“utility”)
and the actual value of money is based on rational calculation. The theory has
hold up until today, although its foundation begins to show serious cracks,
thanks to the work of Daniel Kahneman, Amos Tversky and others. It will need a
thorough study to explain why utility theory could stand so long (and it still
stands), but that’s another problem than what I want to treat here. Now I want
to discuss what’s wrong with it. In doing so I base myself on the so-called
prospect theory developed by Kahneman and Tversky and described by Kahneman in
his book Thinking, Fast and
Slow (see my last blog; all data here are from this book).
Last week I showed already that man is not a rational
being but that he or she is often guided by emotions, feelings and intuitions.
Actually I think that it’s often better so and that what is rational is not
always what is right. Here I want to develop the theme yet a bit more.
Someone offers you a gamble on the toss of a coin. If
the coin shows tails, you lose € 100,-, and if it shows heads you win € 150,-.
Would you accept it? The expected value of the gamble is positive, for you can
gain more than you can lose. Therefore a rational person in the sense of the
utility theory would accept it and that’s also what your System 2 tells you to
do. However, probably you’ll decline, since your System 1 doesn’t like it. Most
people stick to what they have and are afraid to lose it. The psychological
cost of losing is bigger than the psychological benefit of gaining. This brought
Kahneman to rule one – as I call it – of the prospect theory: Losses loom
larger than corresponding gains, or people are loss averse. Of course, if the
possible gain is high enough, you’ll accept the gamble. According to Kahneman
the gain must be about € 200,- or more in the example. However, in some cases
you’ll never accept the gamble, for instance if it is about losing everything
you have or gaining € 10 mln.
Now (1) you are given € 1000,- in addition to what you
have plus you are asked to choose one of these options: 50% chance to win €
1000,- or getting € 500,- for sure. Or (2) you are given € 2000,- in addition
to what you have plus you are asked to choose one of these options: 50% chance
to lose € 1000,- or lose € 500,- for sure.
According to utility theory there is no difference
between (1) and (2): Either you’ll be richer by € 1500,- or you accept a gamble
with equal chances to be richer by € 1000,- or € 2000,-. Nevertheless, most
people prefer the sure thing in case 1 and the gamble in case 2. This leads to
rule two of the prospect theory: The reference point from which options are
valued determines your preferences.
This is not pure theory but it works also in practice.
For example, you got a job in another town and you are going to move and must
sell your house. For a rational agent the price to ask for the house should be
determined by the current market price for such houses. Nevertheless, you’ll
ask more if the current market price is lower than what you paid for your house
ten years ago. Moreover, you are less willing to lower your asking price in
this case than in case what you paid ten years ago was below the current price:
Your reference point determines what you ask and you are loss averse. Or
another instance – a personal one: During several years car dealers put cards
under the windscreen wipers of my old car proposing to buy it for a good price.
From the point of utility theory it would have been rational to sell my car,
but I didn’t, for I stick to what I have.
Traders behave more in agreement with the utility
theory than casual sellers and buyers. In fact this is another argument against
the utility theory, for it illustrates that its applicability is dependent on people’s
attitudes towards value and money. Also experiments carried out in the USA and
the UK gave different results (Kahneman gives an example). But who had ever
thought that what is rational for me is also rational for you?
Source: Especially chapters 25-27 in Kahneman's
book (see last week).
Monday, August 22, 2016
Being rational
Man is a rational being. Also most economists think man
is and they build their theories on it, which often fail. For basically man is
not rational. Or rather most of the time he or she isn’t. Usually man lets
guide him or herself by feelings and emotions, also in economic decisions and not
only in matters of love and relations. That’s what the Israeli psychologist
Daniel Kahneman found during many years of research, together with Amos Tversky
and others. In 2002 he got the Nobel Prize in Economics for it. Actually, it would
have been reasonable that all economic theories had been revised in that light,
but it didn’t happen. As we know since Thomas Kuhn published his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions:
Mainstream theories that have been refuted in scientific discussions don’t
disappear simply because of these
discussions. Often they still remain mainstream for a long time, but they
disappear because the advocates of these theories become older and have to give
their places to a younger generation with new ideas. Mainstream theories are
not toppled but die out.
A standard example of man’s irrationality is the
research finding by Lawrence
Williams and John A. Bargh that holding a warm cup of coffee makes you have
more positive attitudes towards a stranger than holding a cup of ice coffee,
for what has the temperature of your coffee to do with your likes and dislikes?
But this instance doesn’t involve a kind of economic or quasi-economic
calculation. So let me take this case, which I have used before in another
context (just like the cup-of-coffee-case): A driverless, runaway
trolley on a railway is heading for a tunnel, in which it would kill five
people. You are standing on a footbridge above the track. You are slim and
short but a fat man is just crossing the bridge. If you jump on the track, you
will be run over by the trolley, which will kill you and the five people as
well. If you push the fat man on the track, he will be killed but the trolley
will stop and the five will be saved. A simple economic calculation tells you
that this is the best you can do, for the net gain will be four lives saved.
But even if you make this calculation, I’m sure that you’ll not push the fat
man from the footbridge, for your intuition and your feelings, will tell you
that this action is impermissible. And nobody will reproach you that you
didn’t. But what if the fat man stumbles over a stone and will fall on the
rails so that he will be killed by the trolley and the five other men will be
saved, unless you stop him? I’m sure that also then you’ll not make an economic
calculation and that you’ll not think: “I can’t help that he stumbled over a
stone. I didn’t push him, but if I allow
him to fall on the rails, the net gain will be four lives saved, so let him fall.” No, that will not be what
you think, but you’ll follow your feelings and grab the fat man by his collar
and stop him falling, in spite of the loss of five other lives. If you think, you’ll think “I have to
save the fat man.” Nobody will reproach you that you saved the fat man and “so”
let five other men die.
Generally we think that we are rational beings. That
we are conscious, reasoning selves that have beliefs, make choices, and decide
what to think about and what to do. However, psychologists have discovered that
this is not how man is made up. Most of what we do is not rationally and
consciously considered but we just do. We simply follow our intuitions and
feelings, although it can happen that we actively and explicitly think about
what we must do or decide, for example if what we are going to do is not
routine, if it is complicated, if it requires attention or if we have the time
for it. Psychologists say it this way: Our thinking is determined by two
systems, a fast system and a slow system; or as the Keith Stanovich and Richard
West called them, System 1 and System 2. As Kahneman explains in his book about
the subject, System 1 operates automatically and quickly, with little or no
effort and no sense of voluntary control. It’s here that we find our emotions,
feelings and intuitions. System 2 allocates attention to effortful mental
activities that demand it, including complex computations. Here we find our
subjective experience of agency, choice and concentration, so Kahneman. And
it’s this System 2 that stands for the rational man, as understood by most
economists, although it’s actually System 1 that makes most of our economic
decisions. Maybe it’s better so that our thinking is organised that way, for if
it weren’t, we would often lack the time to act. Too much time would be spent
on thinking how to act. We wouldn’t have survived prehistory, for every
smilodon or other carnivore that had passed our way would have had time enough
to devour us, before we had decided to flee or to fight. It spares us also the
impossible decision whether to save the fat man from falling on the railway or
the five other men from being killed.
Source: Daniel Kahneman, Thinking, Fast and Slow. Penguin Books, London, 2012.
Monday, August 15, 2016
On the move with Montaigne
The French philosopher Montaigne (1533-1592) felt most
at ease on horseback. No wonder that he loved travelling. Many trips had a
practical reason. “For business”, as we would say today. But once he made a
long tour through Central Europe and Italy, which lasted 17 months. As a
tourist. The trip would even have lasted longer, if the French King hadn’t ordered
Montaigne to return home for taking up the office of mayor of Bordeaux. He
obeyed reluctantly.
Montaigne started his trip in Paris. It brought him to
Switzerland, Southern Germany and Austria and finally to Rome. He kept a travel
diary, which was not meant for publication, although he used some of his
experiences in his Essays. The diary
was discovered only two centuries later. It showed that Montaigne was an
observant person. He wrote about the towns and the landscapes he passed, the
habits and customs of the people, the food they ate, the design of the houses
and palaces he visited and the rooms where he slept, the beauty of the women he
saw, and much more. On my travels sometimes I pass places where Montaigne had stayed
a while more than four centuries ago. And so it happened also a few weeks ago.
I first crossed Montaigne’s path when I arrived in
Augsburg in Germany and then a few days later again in München. Montaigne
doesn’t tell much about his stay in München, but he gives an extensive
description of his observations in Augsburg, which was called the most
beautiful town of Germany. He tells us that Roman Catholics and Protestants
peacefully lived together and that mixed marriages between them were not
exceptional. The Protestant ministers were paid by the Senate. For Montaigne all
this was remarkable, for in his France one religious war followed another. But in
the Thirty Year’s War (1618-1648) the situation would change in Augsburg, too,
and nowadays it is an almost exclusively Roman Catholic town.
After München our ways parted, for we followed
different roads to the south. However, our most interesting “meeting” had yet
to come. When I went home again after a short visit to Northern Italy, our
paths crossed anew. Now I followed exactly the same route Montaigne had
travelled, but in the opposite direction. In Brixen I came on Montaigne’s road
and I made a stop in Vitipeno. Montaigne had spent there the night. I arrived there
before noon. I walked through the main street with its medieval houses and a
high wall tower on the end. Just when I passed the gate under the tower, its
bells ringed the Angelus. Montaigne certainly must have walked here, too, in
his black or white clothes of a commoner. He preferred not to present himself
as a noble on his trips, so that it was easier to make contact with the common
people. Was the street then as crowded as today? If so, probably most of these
people will not have been tourists, as now is the case.
Next via the Brenner Pass to Austria and Innsbruck. Of
course, I took the old road that was also used by Montaigne. Then the road was
busy and also safe. The latter was not obvious four centuries ago. Today the
road is still safe but it has become quiet, used by locals and a lost tourist
only. Montaigne was right: the road is easy to go, although it is a mountain
pass.
Montaigne and his company stayed two nights in
Innsbruck; I stopped there only for a lunch and a quick visit, since I had been
there before. In the nearby Seefeld it was just the other way round and I spent
there the night. Before I left next morning, I wanted to visit the pilgrimage
church. I parked my car in front of a hotel that dates from the 14th century,
as an inscription on the wall says. Was it here that Montaigne had taken the
lunch? Then he walked to the church where he was informed why it was a pilgrims
place. As Montaigne tells us: “The church ... is ... famous for a miracle. In
1384 a certain man ... refused to content himself on Easter day with the
Eucharist as offered to the people, and demanded to receive that which was wont
to be given to the priesthood alone. While he had this in his mouth the earth
beneath him opened and swallowed him up to the neck, and while he held for a moment
to the corner of the altar the priest withdrew the Host from his mouth [and the
man was saved]. They still exhibit the hole covered with an iron grating, the
altar which bears the impress of this man’s fingers, and the Host of a reddish
hue like drops of blood.” Would Montaigne have believed it? In his Essays he is very sceptical about
miracles.
Now I stood there, 436 years later, on exactly the
same place, looking at the same hole covered with a grid and at the fingers
prints in the altar. Just the idea. Impressed by this “meeting” I left the
church. In the nearby Mittenwald, already in Germany, where Montaigne had stayed
in the inn, I took a cup of coffee. Then our ways parted another time.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)