Two blogs ago I wrote about the Lottery Paradox. I
showed that it was false. However, it stayed straying through my mind, not because
I had my doubts whether it was really false, for it simply is. But I wondered
what went wrong with the paradox and why it is still seen as valid by some.
Well, I cannot give an answer to the latter, but I can say something about the
former. This time I shall be less abstract and formal, so that those readers who
got stuck halfway two weeks ago, will now keep hanging on my lips.
The Lottery Paradox says that we can argue that no
ticket will win in a lottery, although certainly one ticket will do, if the
lottery is fair. What went wrong in this reasoning besides that the statistical
argument isn’t correct? I think that the essence of the failure is in the first
basic principle. It runs, as you’ll remember: “If it is highly probable that p, then it is rational to believe that p.”
The central concepts in this principle are “probable”
and “rational”. But what do these concepts mean? In the argument that is
supposed to substantiate the Lottery Paradox they are not explained. I think
that this is the real reason that the argument goes wrong. Let’s look first at
“probable”. In the context of the paradox it has a double meaning. First it is
treated as a psychological concept but next as a concept from the probability
theory (or from statistics). The first principle of the Lottery Paradox says
something like this: If it is very likely that p will happen, you can suppose that it really will, even though
sometimes it doesn’t. For instance: The timetable says that the next train will
leave within 15 minutes, and since the timetable is usually correct, I can
better go to the station now (even though it may be possible that the rain will
be too late this time). But then, in order to “prove” the Lottery Paradox,
“probable” gets suddenly a statistical meaning, and then the argument is false,
as I explained in my blog two weeks ago. This doesn’t alter the fact, though,
that the psychological interpretation makes sense in our daily life.
There is also something wrong with the way the concept
of “rational” is used in the “demonstration” of the paradox. What is rational
depends largely on the situation where we have to act. Take the train example again.
Suppose that I want to do some shopping in a town nearby. So, I think: “I must
leave home now, although it might happen that the train doesn’t leave within 15
minutes, because it will be late or because the timetable has changed”. Then
it’s rational to go now and not to check possible changes on the Internet in
case there is a train every 15 minutes. If I am wrong, the consequences are
negligible.
Take now this example from my blog two weeks ago: I
work as a security officer on an airport where I check the passengers at the
gate. Say every year ten million passengers pass this airport and only once in
five years someone is caught who might
have the intention to put a bomb in a plane. Therefore, it is highly likely
that the next passenger is a decent person and not a terrorist. Must I say
then: Well, it is very, very likely that the next person is not a terrorist. I
am a rational person and I don’t check her? Of course not, for in view of the
consequences in case she is, it is better to check her, and the next passenger,
and the next … Here it is rational not
to believe that p, even if it is extremely probable that p.
Don’t define your concepts and you can get any
conclusion you like.
No comments:
Post a Comment