A part of the gang
The question of responsibility for an action, in case
this action has been performed on orders from a superior (see last week) is
related to the question whether someone is responsible for the actions of a
group s/he belongs to. I have discussed this theme long ago in my blogs,
especially in relation to the philosophy of Hannah Arendt, so I’ll bypass it.
However, it is generally accepted that it is possible to ascribe responsibility
to a group, as is done, for instance, when a company as such – and not the individual
managers – is sentenced for breaking the Environment Law. Who or what is it
then that holds the responsibility? Or in my example, who or what is it then
that is sentenced? For normally a sentence is passed only for something that is
intentionally done or for what is the result of an action intentionally
performed (even if this result hasn’t been foreseen or hasn’t been intended).
Since our juridical system makes it possible to prosecute organisations and
other formal groups, apparently they are ascribed actions and intentions. This
is in line with common parlance, which ascribes intentions and actions to all
kinds of groups, formal and informal. “The football team wanted to win in order
to avoid relegation.” “The gang decided to beat up the first passer-by”. Such phrases
are common use and they have nothing metaphysical and they are seen as
reflecting the facts. Nevertheless, I think that it is reasonable to ask what
we mean by them. For it’s not Local United that will do its utmost in order to
avoid relegation but John, Pete, Charles and the others will do and kick the
ball. And it is the same for the gang. For if John, Pete and Charles form a
gang after the match (which they have lost) and then attack Henry, the first
passer-by who happens to be also the goal keeper of the opponent, it is not a mysterious
unity that hurts Henry intentionally, but there are three men of flesh and
blood who do.
I think the problem is this. On the one hand a
group is made up of individuals agents and it is they who act. On the other
hand a group is a real social phenomenon and what a group does cannot be
explained by referring to individual agents and simply put them together. For
if we see groups only as an aggregate of individual agents, we get something
like this: Agents have individual intentions and when they act together they
have joined their intentions and have developed a joint commitment. On base of
this joint commitment a group intention is formed. This is basically the
approach of present-day philosophers like Raimo Tuomela or Michael E. Bratman.
A typical case discussed by them is painting a house together. The approach
sounds quite Thatcherian, for in the end it sees cooperating only a matter of
bringing people together in the right way (and that’s why Thatcher thought that
there are no societies but only individuals – and families at most). What this
approach forgets, however, is that intentions and the ways they are put
together do not come out of the blue. They are based on the possibilities,
rules, associations etc. that an agent happens to find already present when s/he
“decides” to act or develops intentions. It is this what is already there that determines
and structures what an agent wants to want (and not just wishes to want) and
what this agent factually can do and will do (within a certain latitude; it’s
true). These “existences” or “availabilities” or how we would call them
(structure, culture) are the foundations of our we-intentions or group
intentions. It’s an idea that is a consequence of Anthony Giddens’s structuration
theory and actually it is a concise rephrasing of this theory in a
we-intentional wording. It sounds quite Marxian, indeed, but it is Marxian only
for a part. For it is not without reason that I said that an agent has a
certain latitude when s/he is going to act in a certain situation. For every
situation where an agent has to act needs both to be interpreted (“what am I
supposed to do?”; “what can I do?”; etc.) and it leaves room for choices: our
elbow room. Sometimes our elbow room is limited; sometimes it is very large.
And here, and especially in the latter case, the first (“Thatcherian”) approach
becomes valid, namely the freedom to choose our own joint intentions and
commitments. Only then and there we can say: we can leave it or we can take it.
Only then and there we can jointly put our individual intentions together so
that we get a we-intention, for instance for painting our house together. It’s
a thing that every free rider knows.
No comments:
Post a Comment