Paradoxes are a type of puzzle cases not mentioned on
the website on action puzzles in my last blog. Nevertheless, they can be useful
in clarifying concepts in the philosophy of action. I suppose that every reader
of this blog will know the most famous of all paradoxes, the Liar Paradox:
Epimenides said: Every man from Crete is a liar. The paradox becomes clear, if
we know that Epimenides himself is a man from Crete.
I have discussed already extensively a well-known paradox
in my blogs above, namely the Ship of Theseus, which is also known as Theseus’
paradox. Also one of the leading ideas in the philosophy of action actually is
nothing but a kind of paradox, namely the idea that what we do – our actions – is
dependent on the way we describe it. This idea has been introduced by Elizabeth
Anscombe. Here I’ll use the version of E.J. Lowe: “A man is described as poisoning
the inhabitants of a house by pumping contaminated water in its supply from a
well, which the inhabitants drink with fatal consequences. There are various
ways of describing what this man is doing: ... moving his arm, ... depressing
the handle of the pump, ... pumping water from the well, contaminating the
water-supply ..., ... poisoning the inhabitants of the house, ... killing the
inhabitants ... [A]re these six different
things he is doing, or just six different ways of describing one and the same
thing?” (p. 240) In the former case, we would call him a juggler, so Lowe, but
also the latter case – the one accepted in the philosophy of action – is problematical.
Moving his arm is considered then to have different descriptions, but suppose
that we want to know when and where the man is killing the inhabitants of the
house. Depending on the way we describe what the man is doing, he kills them at
different places and at different times, for the arm-moving takes place outside
the house and the killing (which take place later) occurs within the house.
(pp. 240-241) “So, it seems, we have to say that the man kills the inhabitants
outside the house and quite some time before they die. But that is surely
absurd”, so Lowe (p. 241). Lowe presents an alternative approach to resolve the
paradox, but I refer those interested in it to Lowe, for here I want to talk
about paradoxes.
I end this series of blogs on puzzle cases with a
paradox that can be used to cast light on the idea of intention. The question
is: Can we intend what we surely will not do? Generally philosophers of action
support the view that intending to do a supposes minimally the absence of the
belief that one will not a. However, take this paradox, which is known as the
toxin paradox and which has been developed by G. Kavka (here quoted from an
article by Stephanie Rennick): “You are offered a million dollars to form the
intention of drinking a vile potion which, though not lethal, will make you
unpleasantly ill. Once you have formed the intention the money is handed over,
and you are free to change your mind. The trouble is that you know this, and it
will prevent you from forming the intention, since you cannot intend to do what
you know you will not do”.
This brings me back to the question whether I can try
to do what I cannot do, discussed in my blog last week. Suppose now that I know
that I cannot break the world record 5.000 m running, if my personal record is
still three minutes slower than the world record after many years of hard
training. Can I say then that nevertheless I can try to break the world record?
Just as we cannot intend to do what we know we’ll not do, we cannot try to do
what we know for sure we cannot do. Nevertheless I think there is much truth in
the conventional wisdom saying “who doesn’t try doesn’t win”, even if you know
that you have no chance.
Sources: - E.J. Lowe, An introduction to the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000 (https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=mH12kYm1RKAC&lpg=PA242&dq=%22individuation+of+actions%22+lowe&pg=PA240&hl=nl#v=onepage&q&f=false).
- Stephanie Rennick, “Things mere mortals can do, but philosophers can’t”, http://analysis.oxfordjournals.org/content/75/1/22.full.
No comments:
Post a Comment