The readers of my blog last week may think that it’s a
strange view that there are actually no pure individual intentions and actions.
How can this be so if most of the time it’s the agent who decides to act here
and now? However, just after I had finished the draft of that blog I read in
Julian Baggini’s Freedom Regained (London:
Granta, 2015) a passage that clearly illustrates what I mean. Therefore, let me
quote a big part of it. But first a remark: I had thought out the mainline of
this blog already before the Orlando club shooting took place, so it’s mere
chance that in the quotation such a shooting is used as an example.
Here is the quote from Baggini, pp. 201-2:
“[In] the shootings ... at Virginia Tech in April 2007[,]
Seung-Hui [Cho] killed thirty-two people and injured seventeen others before
committing suicide, in [what was then] the worst massacre by a lone gunman in
US history. The reaction of Hong Sung Pyo, a sixty-five-year-old textile
executive in Seoul, was typical of many Koreans. ‘We don’t expect Koreans to
shoot people, so we feel very ashamed and also worried.’ It was this sense of
shame that led the South Korean ambassador to the US to fast for thirty-two
days, one for each of the murdered victims.
Many Americans were baffled by this, but every expert
on South Korea ... had the same explanation. ‘It’s a notion of collective
responsibility’, said Mike Breen, author of The
Koreans. “I can smell a collective sense of guilt,’ said Lim Jie-Hyun, a
history professor at Hanyang University in Seoul. ‘There is confusion [in Korea]
between individual responsibility and national responsibility.’ As [Tamler]
Sommers concludes, ‘Koreans did not merely feel shame for the act of the
Virginia Tech killer, they felt responsible. They wished to apologise and atone
for the act.’
The psychologist Richard Nisbett has assembled an
impressive array of evidence which suggests that deep cultural differences like
these do actually change the way people think. In particular, the very idea of
who performs an action differs across cultures. ‘For Westerners,’ writes
Nisbett, ‘it is the self that does the acting; for Easterners, action is something
that is undertaken in concert with others or that is the consequence of the
self operating in a field of forces.’ This means that easterners have a sense
of ‘collective agency’ largely absent in the West.”
So far my quotation from Baggini. I think that especially
what Richard Nisbett says about the self clarifies my idea that there are no
pure individual intentions and actions. No individual grows up by his or her
own. A new child is born is educated by the parents and explicitly or
implicitly also by others in his or her environment, like teachers, family,
neighbours and actually everybody in his/her field of life. When the baby has grown
to maturity, the once little child has developed a self. This self has a lone
side and a collective side. The lone side is what the now grown-up person makes
an independent agent, a person who makes his/her own choices from what s/he has
learned – consciously or unconsciously; I am aware that much happens unconsciously
within us –. The collective side is what someone has borrowed from other people
and makes this person connected to the “field” around him/her. It makes that person
Dutch or American; a father or a mother; a man or a woman in the sense of
Simone de Beauvoir; an expert in a profession; and so on. It makes that someone
at the same time is not only an individual agent but also a social agent in the
sense explained in my last blog. Westerners tend to see an agent as a self, so to
see the lone, individual side of the agent. “Tend”, for not always they do, for
why else should parents feel ashamed for the evil their adult children do?
Easterners tend to look at the collectivity an agent belongs to, so the
collective side of the agent. Therefore they often feel ashamed for what a
group member does. Every acting person has both sides. That’s why there are no
pure intentions and actions and why it needs not be bizarre to feel guilt and
shame sometimes for what others have done. Even more, sometimes it can be
strange not to do so, for – ending with a quotation from Baggini (p. 203) –:
“Given what we know about the importance of nature and nurture, for example,
isn’t it actually unreasonable to hold the individual and the individual alone
responsible for all the bad things they do?”
No comments:
Post a Comment