How can it
be that a thing has a meaning and that the fact that it has this meaning can
explain certain effects or is at least relevant for the explanation of these
effects? This question is the central theme in Fred Dretske’s book Explaining Behavior. Here, I don’t want
to discuss this interesting philosophical work, but only one of its theses,
namely that talking about reasons makes only sense, if reasons are causally relevant for the actions they
are reasons for. Is it true?
When asking
the leading question of his book, Dretske had two things in mind. First, the
meaning concerned as such must be
relevant for the explanation of the effects. “A soprano’s
upper-register supplications may shatter glass, but their meaning is irrelevant
to their having this effect” (1988:79). Even if the sounds had no meaning, the
effect would be the same. However, there are cases where the meaning of a thing
is explanatorily relevant, and it is these cases that Dretske’s theory of the
causal role of meaning refers to (1988:77-80). Second, explanatory relevance is
for Dretske causal relevance. As he puts it in his “Reasons and Causes”: “Any
theory of meaning that doesn’t make a thing’s having meaning into a causally
relevant property of the thing (and hence the fact that it has meaning into an
explanatorily important fact about the thing) is a theory of meaning that can
be rejected at the outset.” (1989:5).
When
Dretske talks about the causal relevance of reasons, apparently he implied: 1)
If reasons are not causally relevant
for behaviour, they are also not relevant
in a different way. For if reasons are not causally relevant, although they
are otherwise relevant, we might suppose that Dretske would at least attach
some value to having them in that case, and he would not reject a theory that
ignores or rejects their causal relevance at the outset. 2) If we talk about
the reasons why we do something, this
“why” has a causal meaning.
For
Dretske, reasons are “those content-possessing mental
states (belief, desire, fear, regret) we invoke to explain one another’s
behavior” (1988:79). Particularly, the agent’s reasons are the cognitive
factors and conative conditions that steer his behaviour. The function of the
cognitive factors C or “beliefs” is “.… to indicate the presence of those
conditions that, if the right motivational state is present, will lead, other
things being equal, to M” (1988:105) with M being what is done by the agent.
However, having a belief is not sufficient for M taking place. There must also
be a conative condition or “desire”, i.e. a certain motivational state (D).
Basically, the cognitive factors and the conative conditions determine together
the agent’s behaviour, and so they are the reasons for this behaviour
(1988:105-107).
Take now
this case: A friend of mine calls me asking whether I can come to help him. So,
I take my coat, walk to the shed, and take my bike. Seeing that I want to go,
my wife asks me to post a letter.
What I do
now can be described as 1) posting my wife’s letter; 2) going to my friend.
Take 1). If we apply Dretske’s theory, the cognitive factor is my belief that
my wife wants me to post a letter. I want to do her a favour, and so I have a
desire (conative condition) for really doing it. This analysis seems to explain
my action “posting the letter” (M). However, we must also consider my “second”
action: going to my friend. It can be explained in the same way as the “first”
one, but that is not what matters here. I want to examine the relation between
both actions. If I had not gone to my friend, my wife would not have asked her
question, and I would not have posted the letter, but she would have done it herself.
So I post the letter because I go to
my friend. My going to my friend is therefore a relevant explanatory factor of
my action “posting my wife’s letter”. Accordingly, it is a reason as described by Dretske, namely a “belief”. But is it also a
causal relevant explanatory, namely a
cognitive, factor for my action “posting the letter”? Dretske correctly says
that cognitive factors can be causally
effective only if there is an accompanying conative condition, or “the right
motivational state” (see above). As just said, the conative condition (desire)
in my example is that I want to do my wife a favour. However, the consideration
that I am to go to my friend does neither refer to a circumstance that can
fulfil my wanting to do my wife a favour, nor is it a cognitive factor that is
or can be fulfilled by this conative
condition. As Dretske puts it, it is not an “internal indication of the
appropriate stimulus conditions” (1988:113n). In order to fulfil this conative condition, we need another cognitive factor that does
indicate the appropriate circumstances, in this case that my wife asks me to
post the letter. I go to my friend because he called me and because I want to
do him a favour. It is not my going
to my friend but my wife’s request that is the causally effective reason for my
action of posting the letter; at least in the sense of “reason” given by
Dretske. However, in the presence of another cognitive factor, my going to my
friend becomes a relevant reason for
doing my wife a favour and this is what happens in my example. So, in this case
there is a (cognitive) factor that is a
relevant reason for an action but not
a causally relevant reason in Dretske’s sense.
The upshot is that reasons can be relevant for explaining
of what I do without being causally
relevant for it. Nevertheless, reasons give an answer to the question why I act that way.
References
Dretske,
Fred, Explaining Behavior. Cambridge,
Mass. etc.: MIT; 1988
Dretske, Fred, “Reasons and Causes”, in Philosophy Perspectives, vol.3 (1989),
pp. 1-15
1 comment:
As I see your example, both are causal reasons, and they both need to be there for the action to happen (in the sense of a logical AND).
Post a Comment