Tuesday, December 31, 2019
Monday, December 30, 2019
The self-fulfilling prophecy and the sciences of man.
In my blog
one week ago I presented the example of the global warming deniers – or the
“climate deniers” as they are often called – as an instance of the Pinocchio
paradox. It’s a pragmatic instance of a pragmatic paradox. However, in a sense,
global warming denying (namely that it has been caused by the behaviour of men)
can also be seen as an instance of a self-defeating prophecy. You’ll know that
a self-defeating prophecy is a prophecy that prevents itself from happening.
For example, your daughter spends a lot of time on playing football, so you
warns her: “If you go on in this way and don’t spend more time on preparing
your exam, you’ll not pass it.” It makes your daughter think about it and from
then on she gives more time to her study and doesn’t go so often to her club
anymore, and she passes her exam. What climate deniers do is a bit like this,
but then the other way round: They have been warned that, if they go on ignoring
the effect of their behaviour on global warming, the global warming that they
denied will happen. So the reverse of what they say that will happen, will
happen. It’s a pragmatic reversal of a pragmatic prophecy, which is quite
paradoxical. But that’s how things often happen.
Once we
talk about the self-defeating prophecy, it’s only one step to the
self-fulfilling prophecy, the phenomenon that a prophecy becomes true just because it has been made. In my example
it can also happen that your daughter realizes that she must make a choice. She
is a good football player and she sees already a career as a professional
before her eyes. Or she can opt for an academic career. She decides to choose
for a sports career. As a consequence she doesn’t pass her exam. By her decision, your daughter makes that the
prophecy comes true.
When I thought
of examples of the self-fulfilling prophecy, immediately Oedipus popped up in my
mind. It wasn’t a really original idea, for a bit browsing on the Internet
learned me that the Oedipus myth is often mentioned as an instance of this
prophecy. In case you don’t know it, here it is, very briefly (which I copied
from the Wikipedia for practical reasons): Warned that his child would one day
kill him, Laius abandoned his newborn son Oedipus to die, but Oedipus was found
and raised by others, and thus in ignorance of his true origins. When he grew
up, Oedipus was warned that he would kill his father and marry his mother.
Believing his foster parents were his real parents, he left his home and
travelled to Greece, eventually reaching the city where his biological parents
lived. There, he got into a fight with a stranger, his real father, killed him
and married his widow, Oedipus’ real mother. Never try to escape your fate, is
what the Greek want to say here. In this blog the relevance of this story is
how Oedipus fulfilled a prophecy that he tried to escape just by his behaviour.
Because of this Greek myth, Karl R. Popper called
the self-fulfilling prophecy the “Oedipus effect”, a term which he introduces
in The Poverty of Historicism
(although he had used the idea already in The
Open Society and its Enemies). In his intellectual autobiography Unended Quest he says about it (pp.
121-2 in my 1980 edition): “One of the ideas I had discussed in The Poverty
was the influence of a prediction upon the event predicted. I had called this
the ‘Oedipus effect’, because the oracle played a most important role in the
sequence of events which led to the fulfilment of its prophecy. … For a time I
thought that the existence of the Oedipus effect distinguished the social from
the natural sciences. But in biology, too—even in molecular
biology—expectations often play a role in bringing about what has been
expected.” It’s a pity that Popper doesn’t say which cases in biology he had in
mind, for the essence of the distinction between the social sciences and the
natural sciences is not simply in the way as Popper interprets the
self-fulfilling prophecy. As far as I can remember, Karl-Otto Apel has made
this clear, but I couldn’t find the passage where he does, but this is how I
see it. In the “Oedipus interpretation” of the self-fulfilling prophecy it is
so that Oedipus knows about the prophecy and just by his try to escape it, it
is fulfilled. But actually it is not Oedipus himself who fulfils the prophecy,
but that the prophecy comes true happens
to him. Not knowing that his foster parents were not his real parents, he
could not intentionally realize or prevent the fulfilment of the prophecy. However,
in my example of the father who warns his daughter that she’ll not pass her
exam, if she goes on to spend so much time on playing football, the daughter
has a real choice and she takes a conscious
decision. This conscious decision
makes the case of the daughter different from Oedipus’ case. It’s true that
Oedipus consciously left his foster parents, consciously killed a stranger and
consciously married the stranger’s widow, but he didn’t consciously kill his
father and consciously marry his mother, for had he known who they really were,
he wouldn’t have killed the stranger and married his widow. So, it’s not the
Oedipus effect, and the self-fulfilling prophecy in general, that distinguishes
the social from the natural sciences, but it is the possibility to influence
predicted effects in a conscious way
that makes the social sciences different from the natural sciences. And this
phenomenon doesn’t make only the social sciences different from the natural sciences
but it holds for all sciences of man.
Monday, December 23, 2019
The Pinocchio paradox
You’ll certainly have heard of the Liar paradox:
“All Cretans are liars”, Epimenides – himself a Cretan – said. But this
utterance contains a contradiction, for if the sentence is true, Epimenides
does not lie, while he says he does. And if he lies, it’s just a confirmation
of the statement, so not a lie. Since the days of Epimenides (who lived circa
600 BC) philosophers have discussed a lot about the Liar paradox and developed
several variants. Do you know the Pinocchio variant?
Once the logician Peter Eldridge-Smith
explained the Liar paradox to his children and asked whether they knew a
version of their own, so he tells us in a paper with his daughter Veronique as
co-author. Veronique replied: “Pinocchio says ‘My nose will be growing’.” I
assume that you’ll know the story of Pinocchio, whose nose grows every time he tells
a lie. Since the use of the future tense makes the statement a bit complicated,
the father changed it into “Pinocchio says ‘My nose is growing’.” And here we
have the Pinocchio paradox. As Peter Eldridge-Smith explains: “So, Pinocchio’s
nose is growing iff it is not growing. It is clearly a version of the Liar [paradox].”
However, there is an important difference between the original Liar paradox and
the Pinocchio paradox. The former is semantic: It is about what the speaker
(Epimenides in my example) says and the meaning of his (or her) words. But in
what way ever we interpret “my nose is growing”, it is not semantic for it is
not about the meaning of words. “My nose is growing” is a statement about a
fact, which may be the case or may not be the case. Therefore, we could call
this paradox pragmatic (in distinction to a semantic paradox). Anyway, it is a
real paradox, for if Pinocchio says that his nose grows and he speaks the truth,
it will not grow. But if his nose doesn’t grow, when Pinocchio utters this
sentence, the sentence is false and so Pinocchio lies and his nose must grow. Voilà.
After a discussion about some logical
implications of the Pinocchio paradox, Peter Eldridge-Smith writes against the
end of his paper: “The Pinocchio paradox raises a purely logical issue for any metalanguagehierarchy solution, strict
or liberal. The Pinocchio scenario is not
going to arise in our world, ...” (the italics are mine). Is it true? Without
a doubt, there are no Pinocchios in this world: There is nobody whose nose will
grow if and because s/he tells a lie. Nevertheless, Pinocchio scenarios do
exist. One of the main political issues in present politics is the fact of the
global warming. It’s a theme on local levels, national levels, regional levels
and globally. All scientific data make clear that it is not a mere opinion that
the world gradually becomes warmer and that man is the main cause of this
global warming. It is a fact. Therefore, the statement “Man is the main cause
of the present global warming” (the “global warming statement” for short) is
true. But alas, there are always people who deny what is clearly true, and so there
are still many people who deny the global warming statement, and these people
happen to be still quite influential. Let me call them “global warming
deniers”. If these global warming deniers will determine global policy, they
will take no measures to stop the man-caused global warming and the earth will
keep warming up. However, if those who endorse the global warming statement
will gain the upper hand and will determine global policy, they’ll take all
kinds of measures that will stop the global warming and then the earth will not
warm up any longer. Briefly: If those who deny the global warming statement
win, there’ll be a global warming caused by man; if those who endorse the
global warming statement win, there’ll be no such global warming. This is clearly
a version of the Pinocchio paradox. However, I don’t doubt that there are more
realistic instances of this paradox, for this world is full of lies.
Source
Peter Eldridge-Smith, Veronique Eldridge-Smith,
“The Pinocchio paradox”, in: Analysis,
Volume 70, Issue 2, April 2010, Pages 212–215.
Friday, December 20, 2019
Merry Christmas and Happy New Year
Merry Christmas and a Happy New Year to all my readers!
Don't forget to read my next blog on the Pinocchio Paradox.
Monday, December 16, 2019
Sadness
I think that most readers of this blog don’t
know that I am interested in the First World War (1914-1918). I’ll not tell
here how this came about but the result is that many years ago I begun to take
photos of monuments and sites related to this war, which I upload to a special
section of my website (you’ll find them here: http://www.bijdeweg.nl/WO1-Inleiding.htm;
the explaining texts are in Dutch, but just follow the links). In the meantime
my website contains about 800 such photos. However, this is only a fraction of
what can be photographed of this war. So now and then I travel to the battle
fields of the Westfront in Northern France and Belgium – or elsewhere – in
order to take new pictures for my website. Or I take pictures of those
countless monuments behind the former frontlines, which you find everywhere in
Europe (and outside Europe as well). Last month my wife and I made again such a
trip. This time we went to the battle fields of the First Battle of the Marne
(September 1914) and the Second Battle of the Marne (May-August 1918),
northeast of Paris not far from Reims. We travelled around there, looked for
and looked at the monuments and visited many war cemeteries as well (it’s
unbelievable how many war cemeteries there are along the former Westfront and
how many soldiers died there). And I took many photos, of course. However, for
me, such a visit to battle fields is not an emotionally neutral affair. Since I
always try to imagine how it must have been there in those days of the war, I
see the many wounded lying and dying in the fields and the trenches. I see the
many many dead everywhere on the ground. So one week being there is long enough
for me, for it makes me very sad.
Now I am home again and I “must” write my
weekly blog. Thinking of my trip to the Westfront, I thought that it would be a
good idea to write about emotions, and especially about sadness. So I looked up
Aristotle says about emotions. I found that in the Nicomachean Ethics he calls them “feelings accompanied
by pleasure or pain” and that he also says “By emotions I mean appetite, anger,
fear, confidence, envy, joy, love, hatred, longing, emulation, and pity”.
(1105b21) In his Rhetorica he even
gives a list of fourteen emotions. Next I took Spinoza’s Ethics from my bookcase, where I read that for him sadness (or
pain) is one of the basic emotions. It signifies “a passive state wherein the
mind passes to a lesser perfection.” (Part III, prop. XI, note). Or should it
be better to write about emotions and sadness by discussing Martha Nussbaum’s
book Upheavals of thought? It’s
another option. But would these words really capture what emotion is and
especially what sadness is? Then I realized that often a picture says more than
643 words (the number of words in this blog). Actually, pictures can better express
what emotions are than words can do. So this time you get a pictorial blog.
Look at the emotional photo here on the top of this blog, look at the face of
this soldier carrying his dead comrade, and you know what sadness is. (click on
the photo, in order to see it better; use the escape button – not the backspace – in order to return to this
blog).
***
Description
of the monument
Monument for the 42th US Division (the Rainbow
Division), situated 8 km south of Fère-en-Tardenois in the Aisne department in
France. It represents a sergeant from the 167e regiment from Alabama who
carries a comrade fallen during an attack on a nearby farm, 25-26 July 1918.
The bronzed statue has been made by Britannique James Buttler and it has been inaugurated
on 12 November 2011.
Saturday, December 14, 2019
10,000 views !
It’s unbelievable: One of my blogs got
10,000 views! My blog “I act, therefore I am” passed this magic limit today. Do
you want to read it, too? Here it is:
Enjoy it!
Monday, December 09, 2019
Alternative knowledge
What do we
know? It’s an intriguing question, also for philosophers. Once I discussed this
case: My wife and I are driving home on a Friday afternoon and stop at the bank
to deposit our paychecks. However, there was a long queue in front of the
counter, so I said: “I’ll do it tomorrow. I know that the bank will be open.” But
my wife says: “Maybe the bank won’t be open on Saturday. Maybe it has changed
its opening hours.” Should I check it? If I am in a hurry and can deposit my
paychecks also on Monday, in case the bank happens to be closed tomorrow, I’ll
not check it. If it is important to deposit my paychecks before the weekend, I’ll
do. In other words: What I know depends on the context. (for a full explanation
see my blog dated 12 December 2011: http://philosophybytheway.blogspot.com/2011/12/what-do-we-know.html)
Contextuality
can affect what you think you know. Possible alternatives are another condition
that can affect it, as Fred Dretske has made clear in his article “Epistemic
Operators”. To illustrate this he discusses a “silly” example, as he calls it, although
it is no more silly than many other philosophical examples. In short, it is
this:
“You take
your son to the zoo, see several zebras, and, when questioned by your son, tell
him they are zebras. Do you know they are zebras? Well, most of us would have
little hesitation saying that we did know this. We know what zebras look like,
and, besides, this is the city zoo and the animals are in a pen clearly marked
‘Zebras.’ Yet, something’s being a zebra implies that it is not a mule and, in
particular, not a mule cleverly disguised by the zoo authorities to look like a
zebra. Do you know that these animals are not mules cleverly disguised by the zoo
authorities to look like zebras?” (p. 39)
Probably
you’ll answer this question with “Yes”, for you simply don’t find the idea that
the “zebra” is a mule in disguise reasonable. If Dretske hadn’t asked this
question, it wouldn’t simply have come to your mind that the zebra might be a
mule in disguise. And why should the zoo authorities deceive you? And is it
really possible to disguise a mule that way that you’ll not notice it? Etc. In
other words, what you believe to be true in this case, depends on what you
think what the plausible alternatives are. You “know” that the animal in the
zoo is a zebra, for what else would it be? (or so you think). But you don’t
have checked it. So even if the animal is a zebra, actually you don’t know.
For, as Dretske says, “the question here is not whether [the] alternative is
plausible, not whether it is more or less plausible than that there are real
zebras in the pen, but whether you know
that this alternative hypothesis is false.” (ibid., italics Dretske) Nevertheless, we think that we know, or as
Dretske says a few lines hereafter: “[W]e simply admit that we do not know that some ... contrasting ‘skeptical
alternatives’ are not the case, but
refuse to admit that we do not know what we originally said we knew.” (ibid., italics Dretske)
What we
think to know depends on the alternatives we judge relevant. That’s why this
approach of knowledge is called the “Relevant Alternatives Theory”. But since
at first sight non-relevant or left out alternatives might be true, it may always
happen that we don’t know what we know, even if we belief that our knowledge is
justified.
Sources
- Dretske, Fred, “Epistemic Operators”, in his Perception, Knowledge and Belief.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000; pp. 38-40. You can find it
also here: https://people.ucsc.edu/~farkas/sclp/papers/Epistemic_Operators.pdf
Monday, December 02, 2019
Standing on the shoulders of giants: Montaigne and Descartes
We all stand on the shoulders of others. In
my blog last week, we have seen how Wittgenstein has been influenced by
Spinoza, albeit only a little bit. However, with the exception of a short
remark in his personal diary Wittgenstein doesn’t mention Spinoza in his work, just
as he mentions hardly any other name in his writings. As for this he should have
patterned himself on Montaigne, one of the first modern philosophers.
Montaigne’s Essays are full of
quotes. He mentions always the authors who stimulated him to develop his ideas.
For a big part his Essays are a debate
of Montaigne with his predecessors and we see how Montaigne grows by it.
On the other hand, Montaigne had and still
has an impact on thinkers after him. Especially during the first years after
his death he had, but actually his influence extends till this day. Christophe
Bardyn – the most important shoulder for this blog – writes in his splendid
Montaigne biography that the Essays
were widely read in the seventeenth century, even to that extent that one could
promote the reading of one’s own work just by referring to Montaigne (a trick
that is still applied: Write how your book relates to other important works,
and the chance that it will be read increases). Two of his most important
readers in those days were Blaise Pascal and René Descartes. A few years ago I
have written already about the influence of Montaigne on Pascal (see my blog dated
23 December 2013), although Pascal called the Essays a “foolish project”, since it was not done to write about
yourself, he said. Anyway, the impact of Montaigne on Pascal is explicit. On
the other hand, as Bardyn notes, the indebtedness of Descartes to Montaigne is
inconspicuous and not properly expressed, although it is decisive. It’s mainly
indirect. For example, actually the whole Discourse
on the Method is an application of Montaigne’s idea of doubt on the
foundations of the knowledge of his time, but Descartes doesn’t mention
Montaigne’s name in this grounding work. By using passages and ideas from the Essays without crediting the source,
today Descartes would risk being accused of plagiarism. Even more, Descartes’s indebtedness
to Montaigne if not his plagiarism starts already in the first sentence of the Discourse, where he writes:
“Good sense is the best shared-out thing in
the world; for everyone thinks he has such a good supply of it that he doesn’t
want more, even if he is extremely hard to please about other things.” It seems
to be an original if not brilliant intro for what would become one of the most
influential philosophical works in history, but Montaigne had written already
before him:
“’Tis commonly said that the justest
portion Nature has given us of her favours is that of sense; for there is no
one who is not contented with his share: is it not reason? whoever should see
beyond that, would see beyond his sight.” (Essays,
book II, 17).
It is as if Descartes wanted to profit by
Montaigne’s popularity without mentioning his name. Or he wanted to appear more
original than he really was. But when Descartes would have mentioned his
sources, nobody would have detracted even a little bit from his achievements.
We all stand on the shoulders of others, or
as Isaac Newton said it: “If I have seen further it is by standing on the
shoulders of giants.” In other words, everything we do we couldn’t have been done
without what our predecessors had done before us. By speaking of “giants” and
not simply of “others” Newton implicitly acknowledged that his predecessors
were greater than himself. And isn’t it so that making a start is often more
difficult than to continue? Descartes was a giant because he made many
important (re)starts in philosophy and science. Paying tribute to his gigantic
predecessors would have made him even taller.
Shoulders
- Bardyn, Christophe, Montaigne. La splendeur de la liberté. Paris:
Flammarion, 2015; pp. 467-8 (my main shoulder for this blog)
- Descartes, René de, Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting one’s Reason and Seeking
Truth
in the Sciences. 2007. On https://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/descartes1637.pdf
- Montaigne. Michel de, Essays. Adelaide: University of
Adelaide, 2015. On https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/m/montaigne/michel/essays/complete.html#book2.17
- Phillips, John, “Montaigne and
Descartes”. On https://courses.nus.edu.sg/course/elljwp/mondes.htm
- Wikipedia
Monday, November 25, 2019
Wittgenstein and Spinoza
Has
Wittgenstein been influenced by Spinoza? It is a question that haunted my mind
already for some time, so now that I had written a few blogs on Spinoza again,
I thought that it was a good idea to sort it out at last and to search for the
answer on the Internet. The result was meagre but the answer is clear: Yes,
Wittgenstein has been influenced by Spinoza, indeed. Probably Wittgenstein has
even read some texts by Spinoza as a schoolboy, for such texts were read on the
type of school he visited. However, how big has this influence been? In fact,
as far as I know and could find out, Wittgenstein mentions Spinoza’s name only
once, and then it is not in one of his philosophical works but in his war
diary. Actually, the reference to Spinoza is a bit weird. Immediately after the
outbreak of the First World War Wittgenstein decided to volunteer in the
Austrian army. Then, on 15 September 1914 – one month in service – he writes in
his diary: “The Russians are on our heels! The enemy is very close to us. Am in
a good mood. Have worked [=philosophized] again. I can work best now while
peeling potatoes. I always volunteer for it. It is for me what lens-grinding
was for Spinoza.” Here, Stan Verdult adds in his blog: “Then you do feel a
touch of identification”.
However,
identification is not the same as being influenced by. If there is any work by
Wittgenstein that has been influenced by Spinoza, it is the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (TLP).
This work has been written originally in German and the title was [translated] Logical Philosophical Treatise. When the
work was published in English, G.E. Moore suggested the Latin title as homage
to Spinoza’s Tractatus Theologico-Politicus
and Wittgenstein agreed. This is not really strange, for not only held
Wittgenstein apparently the Dutch philosopher in high esteem, but a closer look
at the TLP shows that its structure has some similarity with the structure of
Spinoza’s Ethics. Both works are
characterized by a mathematical structure and decimal arrangements.
Also the
text of the TLP shows here and there a touch of Spinozism, especially in
section 6, where Wittgenstein writes:
6.4311 ... If
by eternity is understood not endless temporal duration but timelessness, then
he lives eternally who lives in the present. ...
6.4312 ...
The solution of the riddle of life in space and time lies outside space and
time. ...
6.432 How
the world is, is completely indifferent for what is higher. God does not reveal
himself in the world.
6.4321 The
facts all belong only to the task and not to its performance.
6.44 Not
how the world is, is the mystical, but that it is.
6.45 The
contemplation of the world sub specie aeterni is its contemplation as a limited
whole.
The feeling
of the world as a limited whole is the mystical feeling.
This can be
read as a reference to Spinoza, but unlike Spinoza, Wittgenstein has placed God
outside the world, while for Spinoza, the world is God (“Deus sive Natura”,
“God or Nature”, as Spinoza says.) It’s a kind of criticism on Spinoza. But
Wittgenstein doesn’t mention Spinoza here, for Wittgenstein only rarely mentions
names in his works. To what or whom Wittgenstein’s words refer must be find out
by the reader. This makes Wittgenstein’s work so difficult to interpret and
altogether I think that the similarity between the TLP and Spinoza’s work is
quite meagre. Then, the further Wittgenstein has left the TLP behind him in
time, the less Spinoza we can see in his work. In his other main work the Philosophical Investigations – finished
30 years after the TLP – I can see no relationship with Spinoza at all. My
conclusion is then that Wittgenstein valued Spinoza a lot and that Spinoza’s
thoughts have touched Wittgenstein here and there early in his philosophical
career. More is mere speculation.
References and Sources
- Baum,
Wilhelm, Wittgenstein im Ersten
Weltkrieg. Die „Geheimen Tagebücher“ und die Erfahrungen an der Front
1914-1918). Klagenfurt-Wien: Kitab Verlag 2014.
- “Daarover moet men zwijgen”,
https://webapp.fkt.uvt.nl/gfo/default/index/witi-lk4
- Verdult,
Stan, “Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951)
De wereld is al wat het geval is - één werkelijkheid, een onzegbaarheidstheorie
en Spinoza”, http://blog.despinoza.nl/log/ludwig-wittgenstein-1889-1951-de-wereld-is-al-wat-het-geval-is-een-werkelijkheid-een-onzegbaarheidstheorie-en-spinoza.html
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, http://www.gutenberg.org/files/5740/5740-pdf.pdf
Monday, November 18, 2019
Methods as rules for the mind
When Spinoza was working on his Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, he intended to
write a method that would lead to true knowledge. In this blog I’ll ignore what
true knowledge is. It’s even debatable whether such a thing exists. However,
also in case there is no true knowledge in science and the humanities, we can consider
it an ideal that we strive for. Then the question is: What is a good method
that will bring us true knowledge? According to Spinoza, a good method “shows
us how the mind should be directed, according to the standard of the given true
idea.” (38) But what is the standard of the given true idea? I think that much
can be said about it, but I find Spinoza’s description of method in his Treatise vague and obscure and of little
help for modern thinking. However, Spinoza at least tried to answer the
question what a method is. In later discussions until today it has often been
ignored, even when it was essential (for example even Hempel and Popper didn’t define method). This a strange, for if
we are talking about methods and their use – and methods are the heart of
science and the humanities –, isn’t it then important to know what we are
talking about?
In order to answer this question on method,
I think that especially Abraham Kaplan’s The
conduct of inquiry is useful. In this book, Kaplan distinguishes two kinds
of methodology, namely a methodology that studies specific practical scientific
techniques and a methodology that studies the general philosophical principles
behind these techniques. Only in the latter case Kaplan talks of methods, and
therefore I think that it would be better to call the other type of methodology
a theory of techniques. So while techniques are things like questionnaires,
experiments or scales, following Kaplan we can define methods as the “logical
or philosophical principles sufficiently
specific to relate especially to science as distinguished from other human
enterprises or interests. [They] include such procedures as forming concepts and hypotheses, making observations
and measurements, performing experiments, building models and theories,
providing explanations, and making predictions” (Kaplan, 1964: 23; italics mine).
In short, techniques are concrete and apply to this or that research or
investigation; methods are abstract and basically they apply to all sciences
and humanities or at least to a significant part of them.
Of course, much more can said about this,
but I think it is enough for this blog. Although I don’t want to give an
interpretation of Spinoza’s definition here in the sense of explaining what Spinoza meant, I think that Kaplan’s
description of method can give an interpretation of Spinoza’s definition that
satisfies us. Spinoza says that a
good method should “show us how the mind should be directed, according to the
standard of the given true idea”. (see above) Now we can say that a good method
should give us the logical or philosophical principles and procedures that lead
our mind to true knowledge. In this sense, methods are rules for the mind.
Just one more thing. Some people say that
science is just another opinion. And then these people set the facts as they
see them against the scientific facts they don’t agree with. I think that this
is not a correct approach if you want to reject scientific results. This
approach assumes that science is about facts, although actually science is about
methods (and techniques as well): The essence of science is the right method.
So if you think that a scientific result is not correct, false or even fake,
basically you must not attack the result but the way that led to this result,
so the method. Only if you have shown that the method used is not right, or
that mistakes have been made in its application (or the same so for the techniques
used) you have shown that a result is not correct or even fake.
Sources
- Full texts in English of Spinoza’s Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect:
http://www.yesselman.com/teielwes.htm
- Kaplan, Abraham, The conduct of inquiry. Methodology for behavioral science. Scranton,
Penna.: Chandler Publishing Cy.,1964.
Sunday, November 03, 2019
Spinoza’s Rules for the Mind
The present Waterlooplein (Waterloo Square) in Amsterdam. Once here was
the heart of the Jewish Quarter. Spinoza has passed his youth here and for
some time his parents had a house where now the church in the photo is.
the heart of the Jewish Quarter. Spinoza has passed his youth here and for
some time his parents had a house where now the church in the photo is.
Just like Descartes, also Spinoza has written
down rules for the mind. Or, rather, he had the intention to do so, for like
Descartes also Spinoza didn’t complete his book and he left his Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect – which should
contain these rules – unfinished.
Spinoza seems to have worked almost his whole philosophical life on it, and
judging his own remarks, it had to consist of four parts on method, plus an introductory
part and – I assume –also a kind of conclusion. However, he has written only a
few introductory sections, the first part of the method on “fictive, false and
doubtful ideas”, and a few pages of the second part on the essence of the
intellect. Then the manuscripts breaks off.
For my blog I have read a Dutch translation
of this Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione
with explanations by Theo Verbeek. According to him, the Tractatus can
better be seen as an introduction to Spinoza’s philosophy than a method.
Maybe, he is right, or maybe he comes to his conclusion only because the work
is unfinished. For, indeed, what remains of the book is mainly introductory.
But when Spinoza would have completed the work, maybe we would have considered it
a real method. We’ll never know.
What’s also possible is that Spinoza never
intended this work for publication. Maybe for him it was simply a kind of
finger exercise meant for developing his own thoughts. It could explain why the
work sometimes gives a fragmentary impression and that it is vague and obscure
on many places. In line with this, also the remaining part of this blog will consist only
of some sketchy remarks on the Tractatus, just for giving you a feeling
of what you can expect.
In order to improve our intellect so that we can better understand, we
can get knowledge by four kinds of perception, so Spinoza:
I. Perception arising from hearsay or from some sign which everyone may
name as he pleases.
II. Perception arising from mere experience,
i.e. from experience not yet classified by the intellect.
III. a) Perception of what we call in
modern terms a causal relationship (i.e. we see that one event regularly
follows after another event) or b) perception by deduction (i.e. when we can
infer an event from general propositions).
IV. Perception by seeing the essence of a
thing. (see Tractatus, 19).
It’s from these perceptions that we must
choose one in order to get knowledge (cf.
25). However, it’s not sufficient for getting knowledge. In addition, we need a
method. To my mind, Spinoza says it in a rather complicated way, but I want to
summarize it in my own words by saying that the method we need gives us rules
that lead to true ideas. Actually, Spinoza aims here at Descartes, if I
interpret the text and Verbeek’s explanations well, for what Spinoza wants to
say here is that we need the right perception and the right method in order to
know nature; only then we can understand our mind. Descartes, on the other
hand, starts from the idea of mind – “I think so I am” – and we need this
understanding of the mind in order to be able to know nature. (30-43)
What must a method do for us? Spinoza
mentions four points, namely 1) it must help distinguish true ideas from other
perceptions and help the mind ignore these other perceptions; 2) it must give
rules in order to get perceptions of yet unknown ideas; 3) it must give a plan,
so that we avoid to do useless things; and 4) it must lead to the idea of the
absolute perfect being. However, elaborations of 3) and 4) are lacking in the Tractatus. (49) In part 1, which treats
the first point, Spinoza gives explanations about fictive, false and doubtful
ideas. In part 2, which was intended to elaborate point 2, he starts to write
about the essence of the intellect. Then the manuscript breaks off. In this
part Spinoza explains, for instance, what definitions are. A definition must
give us, so Spinoza, the essence of a thing; it must not be a simple
enumeration of indispensable characteristics. For example, we must not define a
circle by saying that it is a figure in which all lines drawn from the centre
to the periphery have the same length (which is true), but it is – and now I
quite the Wikipedia – “a shape
consisting of all points in a plane that are a given distance from a given
point, the centre”. Next Spinoza gives further rules for a correct definition,
distinguishing between definitions of created things and definitions of uncreated
things. (91-97) However, I’ll stop here my introductory remarks on Spinoza’s Tractatus. I hope that it’s enough for enticing you to
read the book. For although the writing is often obscure and vague and requires
much effort to get a grip on it, nevertheless it’s worth reading if you are
interested in Spinoza’s philosophy and want to improve your background for
understanding his other works, like the Ethics.
Sources
and texts
Full texts in English of the Tractatus: http://www.yesselman.com/teielwes.htm
Full text in Latin: http://www.latinamericanhistory.net/tractatus.html
For this blog I used a Dutch translation of the Tractatus plus the useful explanations
by Theo Verbeek: Spinoza, Verhandeling
over de verbetering van het verstand. Groningen, Historische Uitgeverij,
2017.
Monday, October 28, 2019
Ursula von der Leyen and the Toxin Puzzle
The Toxin Paradox, which I discussed in my
blog last week, seems to be a silly case without any reality. Where in the
world would you find such an eccentric billionaire like Tramp who would give
away a million dollars without getting anything back for it? And how about an
intention that you don’t need to intend? Who believes that such a thing exists
or rather can exist? It’s simply a
contradiction. The only real thing seems to be the toxin, but who would drink
it voluntarily? Nevertheless the Toxin puzzle is not as imaginary as it looks
on the face of it. Even more, the case happens quite often. For example, a
sponsor promises to pay your training for the marathon. You know that a
marathon will not be easy for you, but you also know that later there can be
many reasons to come back on your decision to run the race, and the contract
allows this. You also know that the sponsor will not ask his money back. So you
sign the contract.
A field of society where Toxin puzzle cases
happen very often is politics. An internet website that discusses the Toxin
Puzzle explains it this way:
“The most familiar example of the Kavka’s
Toxin puzzle in the real world is the Political Manifesto. Before an election,
a political party will release a written document outlining their policies and
plans should they win office. Many of these promises may be difficult or
impossible to implement in practice. Having won, the party is not obligated to
follow the manifesto even if they would have lost without it. ... In this
example, the Electorate is the equivalent of the Billionaire, The Manifesto
Promise the equivalent of the intention to drink the toxin and implementing the
policies is equivalent to drinking the toxin.” (see source below, p.31).
When I read this, I had immediately to
think of the recent elections for the European Parliament (see also my blogs dated
15 and 17 July 2019). Of course, each participating party had presented its
political program with promises and plans, and some of these promises and plans
may be difficult or impossible to implement. But that’s not what I am thinking
of. What I have in mind here is the idea of “Spitzenkandidaten” or “lead candidates”.
In order to make it attractive for the electorate to vote, parties presented
their lead candidates and in agreement with the result of the elections one of
these candidates would become the president of the new European Commission (the
executive board of the EU that runs the daily affairs). There were three such
candidates: a christian-democrat, a social democrat and a liberal. It appeared
to be an attractive idea, indeed, and many people went to vote. The election result
was that the lead candidate of the christian-democrats, the German Manfred
Weber, got the most votes, so he should become the president of the new EU
Commission. Or otherwise it should have been the social-democrat lead candidate,
the Dutchman Frans Timmermans, who was a good second. And as a third possibility
it would also have been possible to choose the Danish liberal Magrethe Vestager.
But what happened? The French president Emmanuel Macron had taken it in his
head that all these candidates were unacceptable to him, and so he proposed his
favourite, the German christian-democrat Ursula von der Leyen, who was unknown
to most voters. Now it would have been normal that the parliament would have
said: “We represent the people of Europe and the ultimate power needs to be in
the parliament. So, we the parliament elect Manfred Weber (or one of the other
two Spitzenkandidaten) as president.” But the parliament was afraid to display
its power against such a mighty man as the French president Macron, and it gave
in. In this way it happened that Mrs. Von der Leyen became the president of the
new European Commission, since the European parliament refused to keep its
promise and to drink the toxin.
Source
Wikipedians (ed.), Paradoxes. Situations which defies intuition. On website https://books.google.nl/books?id=DoG8QjF5q58C&pg=PA29&lpg=PA29&dq=toxin+puzzle&source=bl&ots=5gYBSoF8B1&sig=ACfU3U1DPwz7nOBJsjjmFgDKQe14qlHYsw&hl=nl&sa=X&ved=2ahUKEwjL5sHkk6zlAhVRLFAKHc45DB84HhDoATAGegQIBhAB#v=onepage&q=toxin%20puzzle&f=false .
Monday, October 21, 2019
The Toxin Puzzle
Philosophers are good in inventing weird
cases. Especially action philosophers are. Philosophers are serious people, so,
of course, they don’t invent these cases just for the fun of it, although it
can be a pleasure to invent them. No, they do it because they think that they
have an important problem to solve or at least to raise. This problem is then discussed
by other philosophers, and so they fill the pages of their journals and their
books. Since I am also a philosopher – even more an action philosopher by
origin – I like to read such cases and the discussions they bring with them,
and to make my contributions to the debate, sometimes.
Recently I came across such a philosophical
case, and I thought that it would be interesting to talk about it in my weekly
blog. Here it is:
An eccentric billionaire, let’s call him
Tramp, has offered you the following deal. He gives you a vial of toxin. If you
drink it, it will make you painfully ill for a day, but will not threaten your life
or have any lasting effects. Tramp will pay you one million dollars tomorrow morning
if, at midnight tonight, you intend to
drink the toxin tomorrow afternoon. He emphasizes that you need not drink the toxin
to receive the money; in fact, the money will already be in your bank account hours
before the time for drinking it arrives. If you succeed you are perfectly free to
change your mind after receiving the money and not drink the toxin. (The presence
or absence of the intention is to be determined by the latest ‘mind-reading’ brain
scanner). You accept the offer. (Adapted from the original case by Gregory S.
Kavka, see note)
So far so good, and nothing seems so easy as
earning the money and become a millionaire. Is it? In the remaining part of his
article Kavka discusses why it is not, for actually it is impossible to intend to
drink the toxin. I’ll pass over the details, but the essence is this. A
reasonable person can seriously and honestly develop an intention to perform a
certain action but s/he cannot develop such an intention if beforehand s/he
knows already s/he’ll not perform the
action because of its nasty consequences. For it is part and parcel of an
intention that you seriously have made up your mind to do what you intended,
but before you have developed your intention you had already decided not to
perform the action the intention involves. You cannot intend not to do what you
intend.
The case just described has become known as
the Toxin Puzzle. It’s a puzzle, because
you are asked to form a simple intention to perform an action, which is a thing
you every day do many times. Nevertheless now you are unable to form the
intention. Kavka explains it this way. Intentions are not independent decisions
but are related to an action. But the reasons
for an action are a different thing, and just these reasons for the action are
absent in the intention. Or to put it in a different way: The reason to intend
are different from the reason to act in the toxin case. Therefore, so Kavka, “when
we have good reasons to intend but not to act, conflicting standards of
evaluation come into play and something has to give way: either rational
action, rational intention, or aspects of the agent's own rationality (e.g.,
his correct belief that drinking the toxin is not necessary for winning the million).”
(see note) We cannot have double rational standards.
The upshot is: You cannot intend to do what
you know beforehand that you’ll not do. Or otherwise, you can only intend to do
what you seriously and honestly want to do. If you have to abandon an intended
action, this can only happen for reasons that are advanced after the intention has been formed and not if such good (and
effective) reasons are already put forward beforehand. You cannot honestly say
“I’ll do it”, while you know that you’ll not do it, unless you are irrational.
That’s what this case is about.
Note
Gregory S. Kavka, “The Toxin Puzzle”, on https://www.law.upenn.edu/live/files/1298-kavka-g-the-toxin-puzzle-1983
Monday, October 14, 2019
The art people like
Last weekend I participated in the local
art route. During an art route, all participating artists in a town keep open
house. This involves that everyone interested in art can visit the studios or
workshops of the participating artists, like painters, sculptors, etchers,
jewellery makers, or what else there are, such as photographers as well. Meet the
artist at home and see how she or he works is the idea behind such a weekend.
I, as a photographer, participate already many years in the art route in my
town, and I love it, for it’s always a pleasure to talk with other people about
my work and to explain them the magic of photography. But alas, I don’t have a
photo studio. I have only my cameras and my computer with Photoshop, and maybe
the computer is even more important than the cameras are, for today there is no
photo without a computer. Moreover, I don’t have the space to receive many
people at home and to show them my work place (so my computer plus chair) on
the first floor of my house. But there has always been a solution to this
problem, and this year I was the guest of the local painters’ club, which
gathers in the community centre in my town.
But what to present during an art route,
when you don’t have a studio where you can show and explain the essentials of
your way of working? I can take my laptop with me and tell the visitors how
Photoshop works, for today a computer with Photoshop – or another photo editing
program – is what the photographer’s darkroom was in the past. The darkroom or,
today, the editing program is the place where the photographic idea becomes a
real image. But are visitors of the art route really interested in it? I think
they are not. So instead I always make a kind of mini-exhibition that presents a
kind of overview of my work. I show the best of what I have made since the last
art route and I show also some older work, for after a year, art hasn’t become
obsolete (most of the time) and there are always people who haven’t seen it yet
or don’t remember that they have seen it or who like to see it again. And so I
exhibited in my space in the local community centre my “Herd of Elephants” (https://henkbijdeweg.nl/foto/262888529_Olifantenkudde.html#.XZtzrPkaQkI)
and my landscape pictures, taken with a pinhole camera or a normal camera. I
presented there my Mondrian-like picture of the inner court of a hotel (https://henkbijdeweg.nl/foto/305631891_Galerij.html#.XZt0c_kaQkI).
I presented there also my by Rembrandt inspired self-portrait (not on the
Internet), and my expression of “Homesickness” (https://henkbijdeweg.nl/foto/224795761_Heimwee.html#.XZt7g_kaQkI), inspired by Magritte. I presented also other art photos inspired by myself. In addition, I did
something else. I made a photo series of what some people would rather consider
as documentary photography or otherwise as something that is not “real” art.
For the occasion of this art weekend I made a series of photos with bikes. Yes,
simply bikes. Single bikes as you find them here everywhere apparently lost
along the roads. Parked bikes; damaged bikes left behind by the owners; old
bikes now used as flower boxes. It was a mini-series of ten photos. Moreover, I
added a mini-series of six pictures of refuse. Yes, refuse, as you see it
everywhere in the street.
When the art route began, people gradually
dropped in. They watched with interest the work of the painters and they talked
with them. And they watched my photos in my space in the community centre. Some
talked with me and gave their comments. I was a bit nervous, of course, what
they would say. I always try not to provoke comments, for people must say
spontaneously what they think. Only then they’ll say the truth and say something
more than “I like it”.
From other occasions I had expected that the
visitors would praise my “Elephants” or my “Double landscape” (https://henkbijdeweg.nl/foto/136983510_Dubbel+landschap.html#.XZt42fkaQkI);
or my Rembrandt, my Magritte or my Mondrian. And indeed, these photos belonged
to the best of my work, judging by their remarks. Nonetheless, these photos
were not what the visitors liked most. What they liked most were the bikes and
the refuse. For bikes and refuse is what everybody sees but nobody watches. And
that’s what I as a photographer had done: Watch and photograph what everybody
sees but doesn’t take notice of. Just this made these bike and refuse pictures
striking and made that they drew the attention of the visitors. Art is not only
in beauty, but it can also put forward what everybody ignores. That’s where the
art comes in.
Monday, October 07, 2019
Trying
In my blog
last week I said that usually we don’t say that an action is an attempt. We
just do. But under which conditions is it then that we call an action an
attempt? I think that a good starting point for making this clear is Stuart Hampshire’s
description of trying, which I came across once when I was preparing an
article. We speak of attempting or trying, so Hampshire, when “there is some difficulty and a possibility of failure”: We call an
action a try “whenever difficulty or the chance of failure is stressed”. But this
is only so, if the agent knows what to do and has decided to act: The agent “should
have some idea of how the required result might be achieved and that he should
make up his mind now” (Hampshire 1965:107). And I want to add: The agent has not
only decided to act, but s/he has started the action as well and maybe
already fully performed. Only then there is a try. This addition is perhaps
implied by Hampshire but not explicitly said.
But what
does it mean that a try involves “some difficulty or a
possibility of failure”? As we have seen in my blog last week, an action can
fail for two reasons. This implies that there are also two kinds of attempts. First,
an agent may choose a certain action and perform it. Moreover, s/he knows that
normally s/he is able to perform the action till the end, but s/he is not sure whether
the action will result into the effect desired. For example, a runner wants to
qualify for the championship. She knows that she can do it, but maybe the strong
wind will prevent that she’ll succeed. We call such an action a try, because it’s
not sure whether the desired result will be attained, although the agent feels
sure that the action itself can be performed.
However,
it’s another kind of trying, if the agent doesn’t know whether s/he can fully
perform the action as such. Then the try is in performing the action, not in
attaining the result. For example, the runner just mentioned knows that her
shape is good enough to qualify for the championship. Also the weather is
perfect. However, she has got an injury and doesn’t know whether she’ll be able
to finish the race. She just tries.
I’ll ignore the possibility that both kinds
of tries apply at the same time (the injured runner doesn’t know whether she
can qualify, anyhow), but we have seen here two different kinds of tries or
attempts. In the first case, the try is in the intended effect of the action;
in the second case the try is the action itself. Putting it differently, in the
first case the question is whether the action is the right means (the runner
might try to qualify one week later, when the weather will be better), while in
the second case the question is whether the agent is able to perform the action
itself.
How long does an attempt last? When do we
no longer talk of a try? In case an action is stopped before it has been
completely performed, the answer is clear: The try ends as soon as the action
stops. This is also so if the try is of the first kind: If the action has been
fully performed but we don’t know yet it’s result, nevertheless the try has
ended then. This is the case, for instance, when we have finished the race, but
some other runners not yet; or the official results of the race haven’t yet
been published. There still can be many reasons then that we haven’t qualified,
but our action has ended and the try is over, although we don’t know yet the
result. Try and action on the one hand and knowing the result (so succeeding
and failing) on the other hand have a different time span. It can even be so
that a try has a shorter time span than the action that belongs to it. This is
so, for instance, when halfway the race the runner sees that she’ll not
qualify. She can stop running then but she doesn’t, for she wants to finish
anyway.
Can we try and we don’t know? Sometimes a
person succeeds in spite of herself, but unless she herself decided to make an effort to succeed, we cannot say that
she tried. She just did.
Source
Hampshire, Stuart, Thought and action. London: Chatto and Windus, 1965.
Monday, September 30, 2019
A note on the failure and success of actions
Sometimes an action leads to
a dead end.
Being able
to act is one of the foundations of human life. I think that it’s even more
basic than being able to think. That’s why in one of my blogs I replaced
Descartes’s famous “I think, therefore I am” by “I act, therefore I am” (see my
blog dated 3 March 2008: http://philosophybytheway.blogspot.com/2008/03/i-act-therefore-i-am.html).
Although
acting is fundamental to man, this doesn’t mean that the performance of an
action always goes smoothly. Some actions are better to be described as
attempts that can fail or succeed. Nevertheless, it belongs to the essence of
actions that most of them succeed. Therefore, it is not normal to see each
action as an attempt, before it happens. We just do, and when a normal action
fails, afterwards we may say that we attempted to perform it but failed, but
this doesn’t mean that it is right to say that the action concerned was an
attempt. We just say something like “Something went wrong”.
An action
can fail in two ways. Either it is so that the action hasn’t been finished, or
the action didn’t bring the result we expected or hoped for. In the latter
case, the action hasn’t failed in the sense that it hasn’t been accomplished,
for the action as such is there. The runner has finished the race, but didn’t
break the record. The long-jumper had a personal record but didn’t qualify for
the championship, which was her aim. In such cases the finished action failed
in view of its outcome. The jump is good but it doesn’t have the aimed result,
even though it was her personal best. Or, another example, she opened the
window and fresh air streamed into the room, but the room didn’t cool down,
which was just why she opened the window: The effect was absent even though the
action – in the sense of an intentional piece of behaviour – had been performed
as planned.
What we see
here is that the success of an action is
not the reverse of its failure. For what should “the reverse” mean in this
case? If an action failed, because the intended aim hasn’t been achieved, there
are at least two things that might have happened, as we have seen: The agent has
not performed the action to its end or the agent fully performed the action without
achieving the aimed result. If we should call the latter the reverse of a successful action, there
would be no room for unfinished actions, even though they happen often in life.
But if we should call an unfinished action the reverse of a successful action, there would be no room for a nice
try.
Is failing in acting bad? In a certain sense it is
but not if we keep in mind that acting is basic for existing as a human being
and that also a failed action is an action. Failures belong to acting. Nobody
is perfect and when failing has become inherently impossible, we cannot act any
longer. Then life has ended.
Monday, September 23, 2019
The layers of Pagliacci
The cast of Pagliacci receiving the applaus in The National Opera in Amsterdam
In Leoncavallo’s opera “Pagliacci” the
actors Canio and Nedda act in a stage play in which Pagliaccio (played by
Canio) is deceived by his wife Colombina (Nedda) and kills her. What the public
in this play doesn’t know is that in
“real life” Canio is deceived by his wife Nedda, and that the murder in this
drama is not acted (as it should be) but that it is a real murder: While
playing Pagliaccio, Canio becomes so angry that he forgets that he is acting
and during the play Pagliaccio becomes Canio who has been deceived by the real
Nedda. The border between fiction and fact fades away.
In the opera we see a double-layered story:
The first layer is the play with Pagliaccio and Colombina and the second layer
is the “real life” of the actors Canio and Nedda, who act their lives in this
opera. It’s not without reason that I write real
life between quotation marks, for in this case also the “real life” is a
play. Actually, it’s not difficult to add more layers. For instance what if the
tenor Brandon Jovanovich, who sang the part of Canio, would have been the
husband of the soprano Aylin Pérez (Nedda) and would have murdered her on the
stage when I was watching the opera, because she had deceived him? Then fiction
would really have become fact. But
even without this layer that springs from my imagination there are at least two
other layers, namely the spectators in the opera hall (I and my wife and the
others present in the hall), for during the time of the opera they had stepped
out of “real life” so to speak, and played the part of real spectators (to be distinguished from the actors in the opera who play the parts of the
spectators in the play). And then, of
course, there is also the real world outside the opera building. So we can
distinguish at least four layers, each with their own realities and each with
their own fictions and facts, their own actions and events.
The idea of layers is also thematized in
philosophy. Maybe the first philosopher who did was Plato with his Allegory of
the Cave: A group of people is imprisoned in a cave already since childhood.
Behind their backs a fire is burning and between the fire and the prisoners
people are continuously passing by. The prisoners cannot see what occurs behind
them. They see only the shadows of the passers-by on a wall in front of them.
Therefore the prisoners know only how these people look like and what they do
in an indirect way. For the prisoners the projections on the wall constitute
the real world, since they don’t know the world in another way. Here, we see two
layers: (1) the world of the shadows on the wall and their spectators (which is
the real world for these spectators), and (2) the world behind the backs of
these spectators. However, as the Dutch philosopher Nicole des Bouvrie remarks,
when commenting on this allegory: How does Plato know that there is not yet
another layer, another reality? And indeed, there is at least one other layer,
like in Leoncavallo’s opera. Just like the spectators of the opera in the hall in
the same way the readers of Plato’s allegory constitute a layer as well.
An opera wouldn’t be an opera and an
allegory wouldn’t be an allegory if they wouldn’t stand for something in
reality. And isn’t it so that we all play our parts and that we all have our
realities that we try to keep apart and that often interlock like layers? A job
is often merely a way to get the money to live, as it is for the actors (as actors) in the opera. Our “real life”
– for us – may be at home with our family, or in our club, or elsewhere. And
this “real life” is enclosed by a world outside, like the life of the town
where we live, our country and the wide world, which have a big influence on us
and on what we can do. Real life consists of layers of fiction and fact. For
aren’t we often playing a role in our job, for instance, when we hide what we
actually think in order to avoid a conflict with our boss? Don’t we often
screen off a part of us, so that it becomes a separate layer? (Who of the other
students in my class at school knew that already then I loved classical music
and opera and not, say, the Beatles or the Rolling Stones)?
Layering is a fact of life. Often it has a
protective function, and it simplifies our view on reality. It makes our life
structured and surveyable and helps us act in the right way. This is
exemplified by Leoncavallo’s opera in a negative way: Negative in the sense
that we see there what can happen if the border between two layers fades away
and the fiction of a lower layer becomes the fact of a higher layer. Then we
can get a problem. Examples are relatives or friends who have to do with each
other in different roles. A teacher with her daughter in her class. A mayor who
gives a building order to a friend. A husband who deceives his wife with her
best friend / A woman who deceives her best friend with her husband. Suddenly
the situation explodes. We have a scandal. The business deal becomes public.
The marriage ends in a divorce. In the worst case there is a murder. If this
happens the last words of “Pagliacci” apply: The comedy is finished. La commedia
è finita.
Monday, September 16, 2019
The solar cell paradox
The solar panels on the roof of my house
I think
that every reasonable person will agree that we live in an age of global
warming and that the main cause of this global warming is the behaviour of man.
We simply use too much energy and moreover we use energy of the wrong kind:
fossil energy. In fact, fossil energy is solar energy long ago laid up in the
soil by natural processes. Probably all this energy would still have been there,
if not once, also long ago, man was added to the big number of creatures that
lived already on earth. As all creatures, also man needed energy to live, but
as long as man led a simple life, s/he lived more or less in balance with what the
earth produced. Now you may think that I’ll add: And everybody was happy. Not
true. For many people thought that life could be better, but for this they
needed more energy, not only for cooking and for heating themselves during cold
nights, but for a lot more, like better shelters, making better tools,
producing more food, waging war, etc. In the end man needed so much energy that
the immediate environment couldn’t produce enough any longer. Happily man
discovered that there was a lot of energy stored in the soil: peat, coal and
oil. That was nice, of course, but there was a problem – a problem that was
ignored by man at first, for the simple reason that s/he didn’t realize that it
was a problem: Peat, coal and oil are stored kinds of energy but at the moment
you are going to use it, it is added to the energy that is already freely
present on earth. Before man used this stored energy, the amount of freely
present energy was more or less in balance, and if it wasn’t it wasn’t man’s
mistake. But man begun to use more and more stored energy and more and more
stored energy became freely present. And so it happened that the balance of
freely present energy was upset: The earth became warmer. First the global
warming went very slowly and nobody noticed it. However, it went faster and
faster and finally it went that fast that it became impossible to deny that
global warming had become a problem. It became also impossible to deny that
there was one main cause of the problem: Man, or rather man’s energy
consumption. (As it happens, there are always people who deny that there is a
problem or who deny that they themselves are the problem. Also in this case
there are such men, but I’ll ignore them.)
But where
there are problems there are solutions, and so also in this case. Actually the
solution was quite simple: If the global warming is caused by using stored
energy, don’t use it any longer but use only yet freely present energy. So man
started to develop machines and apparatuses that caught freely present energy
everywhere on earth, and so they made things like windmills, water turbines and
solar cells. But since windmills and turbines are very big and since hardly
anybody can or wants to have them in the backyard, the state propagated and
stimulated the use of solar cells for the common man. Moreover it was made – at
least in my country – that you could automatically sell the solar cell energy to
your energy provider if you produced more than you needed yourself. Therefore
it became very profitable to have panels with solar cells on the roof of your house, for
you saved on your energy costs and you could sell your overproduction. And so,
when you walk through my little town and look at the roofs, everywhere you see
solar panels and you can see them also on my house. Moreover, everybody with
solar panels is happy, for it gives not only a clear conscience because you
improve the environment but you get also a big bank account, for having solar
cells on your roof is big money, so to speak.
When you
have money you want to spend it, or so it is for many people. Therefore, as
soon the solar panel buyers had got well filled bank accounts they asked
themselves what to do with their money. Some bought new fridges, others bought
new furniture, again others booked trips to countries far away, again others took
new cars. Thus it happened that many of those people with solar panels on their
roofs increased their consumption and bought new consumer goods. But alas, we
are still in the age that most consumption goods, also when using self-produced
energy, are made with the help of fossil energy. Moreover, many of such
products still use fossil energy as well, like the aircraft you use for your travel.
To cut a long story short: When people take panels with solar cells, soon they are going to
use more energy than before, which still is mainly fossil energy. That’s what
we see nowadays. And that’s the solar cell paradox.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)