Group mind
One of the
major problems in the philosophy of action is how it is possible that a group
acts while actually the acts are performed by the individuals that belong to
the group. That is, the bodily movements that are interpreted as actions are
done by these individuals, and the intentions that make that the body movements
are interpreted as actions belong to the acting individuals. How could it be
otherwise? Intentions are mental phenomena that are developed in the mind.
However, a group hasn’t a mind and so it cannot have intentions. And without an
intention there is no action. Ergo group actions do not exist, and one step
further is to say that there are no groups.
This
reasoning seems sound, but nevertheless I think that, with the exception of
some other-worldly philosophers, nobody will defend this Thatcherian view. (see
http://philosophybytheway.blogspot.com/2019/01/there-is-no-such-thing-as-society.html
for my rejection of this view). Any person who has his/her head screwed on the right
way, will see that everyone behaves as if groups exist. And if such an other-worldly
philosopher walks through the corridors of a university s/he will meet colleagues
from other faculties who study groups or at least do as if they are real in
their theories and investigations. Sociologists, historians, lawyers, etc., they
all study the activities of groups. Is it then that they see ghosts, or is it
the other-worldly philosopher who suffers from delusions? For, to give some
examples, how it is possible then that a football team wins a match if there
are no groups? For even if it is the centre forward who kicked the ball in the
goal of the opponent, if he didn’t have ten other – or at least six other –
team mates, there wouldn’t have been a regular match. Or, other cases, I cannot
sing a duet alone, and it is almost daily practice that companies are sentenced
in court and that it is the company that has to pay the fine and not the individual
members of the management.
So groups
are real phenomena. Even so, the problem remains then how to explain group
actions if it is the individual members of the group who act. Many philosophers,
sociologists and other scholars and scientists have tried to answer this question.
For instance, I am charmed by the structuration theory developed by the
sociologist Anthony Giddens that tries to tackle this problem. However, here I
want to discuss the approach proposed by Deborah Tollefsen in her Groups as Agents
(Cambridge: Polity Press, 2013), which I find also interesting.
But first
this. In her Persons and Bodies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2000) Lynne Rudder Baker defends the so-called “constitution view”. If we take
Michelangelo’s famous statue David, actually we have only a pierce of marble. Nonetheless
we call it a statue that represents David. It is not only that the marble
represents a person, we say also that it has a head, arms etc, even though we
have only a piece of marble in front of us. Moreover, it’s not the marble that
has a head, arms, etc, but it is David (the statue) who has. Baker explains this
by saying that the marble worked by Michelangelo constitutes David.
This is
also more or less implicit-explicit in Tollefsen’s approach. According to
Tollefsen – and I agree – we don’t ascribe intentions to the brain, even though
the thinking process takes place there. No, we ascribe intentions to the whole
person, and that’s what we do when we try to interpret, understand or explain
the actions and or behaviour performed by individuals. When we want to understand
why an individual acts in a certain way, we don’t look in the brain in order to
know what his or her intentions are but we derive them from the actions and the
situation in which the individual acts. Knowing what a person does is “attributing
intentional states” to her. We ask “What are the constitutive features of our
practice that account for its explanatory power? That is, what assumptions do
we need to make about an agent in order to interpret her behavior successfully?
If interpretation is successful, then the assumptions we make about an agent in
the process of interpreting her are justified.” In order to know why someone acts,
we don’t examine her (or his) brain states, so to the body, but we consider the
person that has been constituted by this body and see whether we can ascribe relevant
intentions to this person.
Following
Dennett, this approach can also be applied to groups, so Tollefsen. Dennett
developed the “intentional stance”. “When we adopt the intentional stance
toward an entity, we attempt to explain and predict its behavior by treating it
as if it were a rational agent whose actions are governed by its beliefs,
intentions, and desires”, so Tollefsen, interpreting Dennett. But if this is
correct, then we can apply the intentional stance also to groups. Groups are
constituted by the individuals that make up a group. Moreover, when we ascribe
an intention to an agent, we don’t look for the way it is formed in his or her
brain, but we ascribe the intention to the person as a whole. In the same way, even
though a group hasn’t a kind of brain (and mind) as an equivalent to a person’s
brain (or mind), nonetheless we can ascribe intentions to a group and treat it
as if it has. We simply must consider the group as constituted by its members
and treat it as a whole.
No comments:
Post a Comment