Thomas Hobbes’s
main work Leviathan is a book about the state. Until now I have written
in my recent blogs about other aspects of the Leviathan, but this time I
want to write on Hobbes’s view on the state. It is especially treated in Part II,
titled “Of Commonwealth” with some important introductory sections in the last
chapters of Part I (“Of Man”).
A man is a
wolf to another man, so Hobbes. We have seen this in my last blog. The
consequence is that society is a war of all against all, or at least it is a
situation of armed peace with real fighting never far away. According to
Hobbes, there are three reasons for the conflicts between men: competition in
order to gain profits; confidence in order to live safe; and glory. This state
of war is the natural state of man. Injustice doesn’t exist: We cannot talk
about what is good and bad or right and not right in such a situation, for
where a common power that keeps man under control doesn’t exist, there is no
law, and where there is no law, there is no injustice. However, people fear
death and they want to live a pleasant life. Therefore they want peace. By
reasoning this way, Hobbes gets at his first law of nature: We must seek peace
and strive for it. However, this is only possible – and that is the second law
of nature – if man is willing to give up as much of his rights and liberty as
is necessary to get this peace, provided that others are willing to do the
same. These two rules are the core of Hobbes’s Law of Nature.
So, people
want safety and peace and for this they have to take the safety and peace of
others into account. This problem can only be solved if there is a common power
and a kind of state, so Hobbes. This can happen only, if men conclude a treaty
by which they hand over their rights to a sovereign or to a leading council.
The function of this authority is to give the people safety, so that they can build
up a good life with which they are satisfied. When people have concluded such a
treaty, they have given birth to the great LEVIATHAN. The authority they have
installed this way contains the essence of the state, or “commonwealth”, as
Hobbes actually says. This essence is “one person, of
whose acts a great multitude, by mutual covenants one with another, have made
themselves every one the authority, to the end he may use the strength and
means of them all as he shall think expedient for their peace and common
defence.” This authority is called the sovereign and all the others are
called subjects. (see the end of chapter xvii of Hobbes’s Leviathan) In this state it is the sovereign who
makes the laws that the subjects must obey. There is one restriction: A subject
keeps his right to protect his or her own life; the sovereign is not allowed to
take the lives of the subjects.
This is the core of Hobbes’s theory of the state.
What remains in Part II of his Leviathan is mere elaboration. It is clear that Hobbes is an advocate of an authoritarian state,
governed by an autocratic ruler, or otherwise by an autocratic council. Although
Hobbes doesn’t say so, implicit in the Leviathan is that he prefers the
former, the one-man autocracy. Once the sovereign has been chosen, the
influence of the subjects is almost nil. Of course, the sovereign has his
advisers and he has to take care of the safety of the subjects and must take
care that they can promote their welfare. He must also respect their lives and
a few other rights. But basically the sovereign rules alone. There is no place
for a kind of democracy or a kind of state without a central authority, like
the Republic of the Netherlands in his days (several times in the Leviathan
Hobbes refers to the Republic). This makes his state theory different, for
example, from the state theory developed by Spinoza not long after Hobbes wrote
down his one. Spinoza discussed several types of state in his Political
Treatise. He clearly preferred a kind of democracy, although he wondered to
what extent it could be realized. Not so Hobbes. A democratic state even didn’t
come in his mind, although there had already been examples of such types of
state. The most famous democracy was, of course, Athens in the 5th and 4th
century B.C. Apparently, Hobbes didn’t see it as a realistic option. History proved
him to be wrong – the history of England and the UK in the first place did.
No comments:
Post a Comment